Collected Thoughts on Satellite Mega-Constellations and my Loathing Thereof

“The new world is online and loving it, the virtual happily edging out the actual. The darkness is shut out and the night grows lighter and nobody is there to see it.” – Paul Kingsnorth, “Confessions of a Recovering Environmentalist” (2010)

“Are modern folk, perhaps, afraid of night? Do they fear that vast serenity, the mystery of infinite space, the austerity of stars? Having made themselves at home in a civilization obsessed with power, which explains its whole world in terms of energy, do they fear at night for their dull acquiescence and the pattern of their beliefs? Be the answer what it will, today’s civilization is full of people who have not the slightest notion of the character or poetry of night, who have never even seen the night. Yet to live thus, to know only artificial night, is as absurd and evil as to know only artificial day.” – Henry Beston, The Outermost House (1925)

 

Collected Thoughts on Satellite Mega-Constellations and my Loathing Thereof

0. Introduction: Crisis in the Heavens

I am writing this piece – based in large part on private notes from 2020 – in the summer of 2022, from a holiday home in rural southern Sweden. I am writing this sentence having just stepped indoors from stargazing on my terrace. The night is dark, the heavens are deep, the Milky Way is clearly visible. The trees now stand as negative space, the jagged outline of the firmament. I take heart in the starry nightscape’s continued ability to enchant. At the same time, however, dark adaptation seemed only to attune my eyes to the ever-presence of satellites. 

I’ve not thought much about satellite megaconstellations over the past two years, primarily due to the fact that I’ve spent these years deliberately avoiding any news about them; the blood pressure spikes never seemed worth it. Satellites, no doubt, are numerous – but how many of these, if any, are due to Starlink, OneWeb, Amazon, and other companies in this new megaconstellation industry? How many more satellites are there now than when I first noticed the night sky, and how rapidly is the problem worsening? I try not to think about it.

In an October 2021 article for Space.com, astrophysicist Paul Sutter provided some numbers from those who do think about it: “There are currently more than 3,300 active artificial satellites in Earth orbit, according to the Union of Concerned Scientists, a science advocacy group. Meanwhile, the scientists behind new research note, generation 1 of SpaceX’s Starlink will, by itself, consist of 11,926 satellites, and generation 2 will have 30,000 more. OneWeb, Amazon’s Kuiper and China’s SatNet combined will deploy over 20,000 satellites.” 

I first heard about Starlink in late 2019, appalled by the news that the launch of 60 satellites “photobombed” the Alpha Monocerotid meteor shower, which was being recorded from the island La Palma – a perennial astrophotography hotspot and birthplace of the “Declaration in Defence of the Night Sky and Right to Starlight” (2007), which declared that “An unpolluted night sky that allows the enjoyment and contemplation of the firmament should be considered an inalienable right equivalent to all other environmental, social, and cultural rights.”

In February 2020, Covid was still something happening “out there,” and Starlink was still in my Facebook feed and on the forefront of my mind. In a moving article for Scientific American, astronomer Ronald Drimmel warned, “Once this satellite constellation is fully deployed, there will be over 100 moving points of light in the night sky within a couple of hours of sunrise and sunset, from any point on the planet. There will be more of them than the brightest stars we can see—the same stars used to delineate the ancient constellations” (“We Must Preserve the Night Sky”).

In March 2020, Covid and its associated lockdowns spread to the United States, and Starlink launches continued (if only we could have sent Elon Musk and minions to social isolate on their precious Mars!), and between the two the looming threat of megaconstellations became the source of an anxiety and dread that was at times nearly overwhelming – much more so than the pandemic itself. I was trapped in a city at the time, and I became gripped by a fear that I would never again see the night sky as 13.8 billion years of astronomical evolution created it. There was a dystopian scenario that replayed itself in my mind: lockdown one day would be lifted only to leave us everywhere immured by the shiny trinkets of technocrats. The world would reopen to travel, but travel as far as we might, we would find nothing but a clearer view of thousands of satellites shot to the sky by a 300,000-year-young species, all within a few years, all within a handful of acts of hubris, greed, and a failure to imagine that anything could possibly matter more than our young species’s newest material comforts and conveniences. And from the most remote corner of Earth, I would fall to my knees and scream to the heavens; I would raise my fist to the sky and wail curses at Elon Musk and his brethren. And I would collapse in the agony of irreversible defeat.

If lockdowns had lasted as long as Covid itself, my existential dread might not have been misplaced. In November 2021, astronomer Aparna Venkatesan spoke at the International Dark Sky Association’s “Under One Sky” Conference, where she warned that we all stand to lose the night sky to satellite megaconstellations within two or three years. As I write this, we may have only a year left – if that – if her prophecy is correct.

But just what is so bad about the loss of the night sky to fleets of bright satellites? whence arises such encumbering angst and dread? Something curious about my revulsion toward satellite megaconstellations is that, on the surface, humans are the only species who are clearly harmed. If the main problem is the loss of the ability to experience awe, wonder, and enchantment, then it seems we’re dealing with a uniquely human problem. And uniquely human problems typically don’t evoke this type or degree of indignation from me. 

Subjectively, it feels as though my loathing of this desecration of the heavens is cut from the same cloth as my loathing of the destruction of wild nature down here on Earth; it hits the gut with a similar strength and flavour. Theoretically, however, the concerns seem as though they must be very different. Ignoring the material used to manufacture the satellites, the fuel used to launch them, and perhaps the clearing of land to create a launch site, the damage caused by these projects doesn’t appear to have much effect on our planet’s largest ecological crises: habitat destruction, wildlife population decline, biodiversity loss, and so on. The despoilment of the heavens isn’t obviously an impediment to the continuation of evolutionary processes, nor to ecological integrity, nor the welfare of non-humans. It might very well be so (cf. §2.3, §4.2), but it isn’t obviously so, and my felt indignation doesn’t turn on contingencies regarding the satellites’ impact on biological or ecological processes.

I do suspect that there are root causes to the crises in Heaven and Earth. The disenchantment of humanity. The veneration of the putatively practical. The lack of wonder at – and thus reverence for – Nature as she is in herself. It all comes back, in a way, to affirmation of the useless (as once was the theme of a short-lived blog of mine). It shouldn’t be surprising, then, that I have no use for arguments against megaconstellations based on the premise that a clear view of the night sky is necessary for useful astronomical observations. When opponents of megaconstellation feel the need to cite their own practical concerns, they risk leaning into the same fundamentally problematic presupposition: that practicality overrides awe and wonder. (I have a special disdain for the argument that the megaconstellations may hinder astronomers’ ability to forecast meteor strikes that could imperil human life; sometimes meteors strike Earth and vanquish dominant species, so just get over it, the way people tell me to get over the non-avian dinosaurs.) 

In the remainder of this post (essay? novella?), I provide a personal story to further contextualise why the night sky is important to me (§1), and I muse on the tragic irony that such an experience of the pure night sky – an experience of natural wonder that ought to be among the most accessible – has already become attainable nowhere on Earth (§2). After that, I take a few stabs at analysing and precisifying exactly what is (morally) wrong with the deployment of Starlink and other satellite mega-constellations: it creates a humanised planet where it is literally impossible to see beyond the works of our own species (§3); it is a particularly bold and crass form of cultural imperialism, deciding for all that the natural night sky is less important than a convenience for some members of Homo sapiens (§4); the values that enable technologists to launch megaconstellations are simply bad values to hold (§5). Finally, I dismiss the inane notion that the “need” for global internet access provides an excuse to despoil the skies with satellite megaconstellations (§6).

1. My Dark Sky Story

Like many dark-sky advocates, I grew up in a rural area. Unlike many dark-sky advocates, however, I spent my childhood ignoring the night sky. Childlike wonder? Ha! I wasn’t sufficiently mature to experience that until sometime in my late 20s…   

1.1 Conversion to the Dark Side

It started by noticing sunsets, which were often stunningly gorgeous even from the urban metropolis where I then lived, and it progressed into sheer enrapturement in the changing colours of the sky through nautical twilight. On clear days, gazing into the sky was a liminal ritual, but as the deep blue of astronomical twilight took hold, it was time to retire to my quarters, for night itself held little fascination in my artificially illuminated downtown neighbourhood. Like most urbanites, I had grown accustomed to perpetual skyglow as what “night” looked like. Yet I did recall “meteor shower parties” at my childhood home – when the adults sat under the night sky on our patio, drinking wine coolers and occasionally shouting “I saw one!” – and I slowly grew curious to re-experience what I took for granted then. 

Having forgotten what I’d lost, it took some time to summon the motivation. I hated driving, and I seldom ventured from my pedestrian radius and a few familiar bus routes. But I did still have a car in those days, and I was in a romantic relationship that sometimes gave me reason to stray from my comfort zone (a little bit, within bounds). So one summer’s evening I suggested to my then-partner that we go to the middle of nowhere in the middle of the night to watch the Perseid meteor shower (albeit with craft beer instead of wine coolers). It proved to be an utterly profound experience, igniting a romance with the night sky that has never left me. 

Leaving my Toyota Corolla by some obscure dirt road, we trudged into what seems to be an abandoned quarry. I’m sure it was not the most scenic spot by day, but on that mostly clear and moonless night, its 360 degrees views were most remarkable, and as my eyes adjusted to the darkness, I found myself in shock and awe – indeed reverie. The meteors themselves were of course captivating, yet even they were not the main source of astonishment. There were stars by the hundreds, thousands, seemingly infinite in their unfathomable depth! And there, clearly visible, sprawled the cloudy band of the Milky Way! This was no photograph. It was no planetarium show. This was the palpable reality that extended before my naked eyes in the warm summer night. The firmament had depth and dimension I’ve never fathomed, and there in the star-studded darkness, I seemed to lose track of the boundaries of my own self and its earthly environs; they faded, dissolved, subsumed into the vastness of space and time – like a transfiguration back into the star-stuff whence our cells once came.

Adrift in the cosmic sea, I was humbled by the ineffable beauty that stretched out far beyond me – with light from long before me – and yet there was also an ease and comfort in the shroud of the night, a sense of homecoming and belonging. I was simultaneously awestruck by grandeur and entirely in my place. It is little exaggeration to call the experience life-changing, a spiritual awakening. The Apostle Paul (then Saul) was blinded by the light; I was brought to my knees by the overwhelming power of darkness. 

Back in my urban apartment, my day-to-day life remained much the same, but with renewed perspective, vitality, and hope – for I knew that beyond the drab monotony and cacophony of the city there was beauty and splendour and sublimity, and I had a mission to return. 

1.2 The Afterglow

I can’t credit the experience for making me an ecocentrist or conservationist; those dispositions have separate roots traceable to interests arising both before and after my Road to Hocking County conversion experience. It did, however, transform me into a dark-sky advocate – from the next morning on. My predominant interests have since grown more earthbound, yet my dark-sky advocacy lingers on; it would be most remiss to ignore light pollution’s deleterious effects on wildlife and ecosystems. I know, moreover, that the avoidance of artificially bright night sky has a salubrious effect on my mental health (and, conversely, that subjection to light pollution has deleterious one). But there was one conclusion that I now must rescind: when the situation on Earth seems hopeless, and eco-anxiety takes hold, I can no longer repose hope in the recoverability of the heavens

For a brief time, you see, it was like this: I had discovered the immeasurable mental health benefits of immersion in the sights, sounds, and smells of the more-than-human world – in the woods, the wetlands, the coastlines – even in the daytime. But this revelation had come as a double-edged sword, for I came to fear the loss of the places and creatures that gave me succour. And the more I depended on them for my wellbeing, the more I became addicted, and the more I became addicted, the more I feared their loss – for the more I feared I couldn’t cope without. 

Consider, for instance, birds. Sometime between late 2018 through early 2019, I became an irredeemable Bird Person. Birds, I discovered, were my joy and my company, and they were always there for me; in difficult moments, a “bird therapy break” could reliably boost my mood like nothing else. Birds were that whose absence caused loneliness and whose presence instantly took it away. Then, in September 2019, an article was published in Science that sent the North American birding community into frenzied anxiety. Titled simply “Decline of the North American avifauna,” the infamous article revealed a loss of 29 percent of the continent’s breeding birds in less than 50 years. And the situation was growing steadily worse, as the Trump administration was pushing along with its rollback of America’s long-standing Migratory Bird Treaty Act (on top of a multitude of other environmental rollbacks). The economy was doing well, or so I was told, and a reelection of Trump seemed imminent. Meanwhile, the rhetoric from the Left only exacerbated my fear for the feathered ones – plagued as it was by anthropocentric “green growth” fetishism and, with it, a staunchly anti-avian tendency to (for example) downplay or deny the very real fact that wind turbines kill birds.

Birds, it seemed, had few friends – not in government, certainly, and not even in mainstream environmentalism – and I began to wonder how much longer I could count on Class Aves even to exist. No, the reason to protect birds is not that I am personally entitled to them as some type of psychotherapy; birds obviously have their own intrinsic right to exist that has nothing to do with me or anyone else. Nonetheless, I came to fear my own future loss at the same time as I delighted in the birds around me. For my own sake, I needed a back-up plan, a fallback option, a source of connection and enchantment that wasn’t bird-dependent… 

And then, despite having resettled in the city, I remembered my resplendent experiences of the star-filled night sky. That, surely, was something that could never be taken away! Not everywhere… Lol, oops.

And so this is the background context of my initial acquaintance with satellite megaconstellations, as described in §0: it was less than three months after the publication of “Decline of the North American avifauna” that I learned about Starlink. And I felt hopeless. It wasn’t supposed to be like this. The heavens were supposed to offer our last bastion of hope. After humanity has polluted, ransacked, and degraded the last square inch of the surface of Earth, and when the last wild creatures lay murdered in their concrete tombs, the heavens were still supposed to be there. There was supposed to always be some vague comfort in the thought that no matter how bad things are down here on Earth – no matter how many forests clearcut, wetlands drained, species rendered extinct – there would always be, if nothing else, the ability to turn off the lights and lose ourselves in the endless grandeur of the universe, its limitless potentiality. We might look up and think that, surely, in this vast universe, there are other planets that harbour life. And surely among these there are those upon which life still thrives and diversifies. And even if it’s the unavoidable fate of each verdant and vital planet that a species like ours will arise as its undoing, there is always the reassuring fact that as we gaze into the firmament, we gaze back in time. Perhaps, for instance, the Andromeda galaxy of 2.5 million ago – the Andromeda we see – still contains such a virginal untainted life-giving world. We were always supposed to have this hope, this escape; we were always supposed to have the sky. 

But suddenly, without warning, we stood to lose even this. Everywhere. I was paralysed; there seemed nothing left to do but watch helplessly as Earth perishes beneath mechanised skies. 

In the ensuing months, the unprecedented disruptions of the COVID-19 pandemic exacerbated my eco-anxiety to a nearly intolerable degree. It welled in the form of more strange apocalyptic thoughts: “What if this is the final spring? What if next year the warblers don’t pass through and egrets and the kinglets and flycatchers don’t return? What if next year the fireflies don’t flash? What if there are no wildflowers left to bloom? What if the evening chorus of the frogs vanishes along with the morning chorus of the songbirds? What if this is the last spring – and I am locked away to miss it all indoors? I, for one, would sooner die from Covid than live to witness the aftermath.”

It turned out that those worries were overstated. Ohio never issued a full lockdown requiring people to remain in their homes. While denizens of less “freedom-loving” countries sheltered indoors, I visited my neighbouring wetland several times daily. The red-winged blackbirds continued to sing. The egret returned. The warblers passed through. The damselflies and dragonflies graced the reeds of the marsh, and then came even the fireflies. Combine that with the guaranteed freedom from most of the tedious and insufferable interactive rituals of humankind, and my spring of 2020 was a time of constant meditative bliss. Almost.

I was still confined to the city under Bortle Class 8 skies, and from my place of confinement, I read the news of the Starlink launches, and post-apocalyptic dystopian nightmares continued – this time, as described in §0, in the form of nightmares about the night.

2. The Tragedy of the Night

“[I]f a man would be alone, let him look at the stars. The rays that come from those heavenly worlds, will separate between him and what he touches. One might think the atmosphere was made transparent with this design, to give man, in the heavenly bodies, the perpetual presence of the sublime. Seen in the streets of cities, how great they are! If the stars should appear one night in a thousand years, how would men believe and adore; and preserve for many generations the remembrance of the city of God which had been shown! But every night come out these envoys of beauty, and light the universe with their admonishing smile.” – Ralph Waldo Emerson, “Nature” (1836)

2.1 The Most Accessible Natural Wonder?

As of 2016, approximately 60 percent of Europeans and nearly 80 percent of North Americans lived beneath skies so light-polluted that they cannot see the Milky Way (see Fabio Falchi, et al, “The new world atlas of artificial night sky brightness,” Science Advances).

The statistics, I presume, are even worse now: the same study found that artificial sky brightness was increasing by about 6 percent each year. While this loss of the night is reversible in principle, a profound shift in values remains necessary to reverse it in practice.

It is a tragic irony, considering that the celestial firmament ought to be one the most accessible avenues for any man, woman, or child to revel in natural wonder beyond the scale and scope of our young species. There are many earthbound phenomena that offer the potential for enchantment in Nature, but the sky has the distinct benefit that it is everywhere. Unlike particular species of animals or plants, ecosystems, geological formations, and so on, the night sky can be seen from anywhere on the planet, at least for most of the year (those summering in the arctic might be temporarily out of luck). In principle, every person on Earth could enjoy an awe-inspiring view of the stars on any clear and dark night – “every night come out these envoys of beauty,” in Emerson’s words – and enjoy this spellbinding view from their own gardens, terraces, or sidewalks. There is no need, in principle, to drive or hike to see the stars. As Emerson wrote, albeit from a bygone age, “Seen in the streets of cities, how great they are!”

Moreover, these envoys of heavenly beauty have the useful quality that they persist undiminished by human interest therein; they would not be threatened by billions of eyes gazing upon them. Even if every person on Earth were to look upward at once, the stars would not flee, frantic and disoriented in the chaos of attention, nor would they be trampled or eroded under the weight of our telescopes. An earthbound wilderness can be “loved to death” by too many tourists vying for their experience of untouched nature, and animals can perish from the stress imposed by eager human observers (witness, for example, the tragic fate of a baby American Oystercatcher at Milford Point following a four-hour stakeout of four wildlife photographers). But the stars and the planets, the comets and the meteors, endure human attention unharmed, and they will continue to do so, night after night after night, however many astrophotographers stay up for an all-night stakeout.

 Stargazing is no substitute to fulfil our needs for connection to the more-than-human here on Earth – not even close – but it may be, in principle, the most accessible source of awe and wonder at that which extends beyond our species (underline ‘in principle’).

2.2 The Easiest Pollution to Clean Up?

We have expelled darkness from most of the “civilised” world for over a century (see Henry Beston’s seminal passage at the top). Even so, however, dark-sky advocates have long taken heart in another fact: light pollution is the easiest type of pollution to clean up, or so we assumed until recently.

All it takes, it seems, is a large-scale blackout. In 1994, when an earthquake disrupted power throughout the metropolis, LA residents called the local Griffith Observatory to inquire about a strange giant cloud in the sky: they were seeing the Milky Way for the first time. A similar incident befell New York City after Hurricane Sandy in 2012. In February of this year, Ukrainian photographer Pavlo Pakhomenko found solace and inspiration by photographing the night sky when Ukraine introduced a country-wide blackout regime; his work and moving story is documented in the article “Dark skies over Kharkiv, Ukraine” recently published on the International Dark-Sky Association (IDA) website. This year’s IDA “Capture the Dark” photo contest honourable mentions also include striking before and after photographs of a programmed blackout in Bariloche, Argentina and a power outage at Iowa State University.

When I joined the IDA less than a decade ago, the morning after my spiritual conversion in rural Ohio, satellite megaconstellations were not yet part of the discussion. Despite the rapid spread of light pollution in recent decades, there was always an optimism that light pollution was easily reversible, if only values could be changed. The night sky was presumed always to be there in the background, instantaneously recoverable to its pristine state. Unlike most types of pollution, light pollution can literally be removed with the flip of a switch – or so we thought until recently.

2.3 Nowhere Truly Dark

Two centuries ago the beauty and wonder of the heavens was everywhere accessible. Two decades ago it was still presumed fully and easily recoverable. And today nowhere is truly dark, not even Dark Sky Sanctuaries in which artificial light sources are heavily regulated. And one of the biggest culprits is not so easily erased, since it’s out of the reach of most of us, up in the sky circling the Earth (and, no, astrophotographers, I don’t mean the Moon). 

Light trespass from cities is one major concern today: the famed dark skies of Death Valley are now violated by the light dome of Las Vegas. Fracking sites are also becoming a major contributor to light pollution in rural areas, as are greenhouses. But literally rising above all other artificial light sources, there is one sufficient cause of the global loss of true darkness: space junk. Anthropogenic light pollution is caused not only by our lights down here at the surface – those easily switched off and vulnerable to the actions of storms or monkeywrenchers – but also by our satellites and other artefacts left up in orbit. Satellites’ bright streaks are only the tip of the iceberg. An even bigger problem is not so overtly striking: space junk increases diffuse night sky brightness by reflecting and scattering sunlight, night in and night out.

 In an immensely important article published in June 2021 (“The proliferation of space objects is a rapidly increasing source of artificial night sky brightness”), Miroslav Kocifaj and coauthors model the impact of satellites on diffuse night sky brightness (NSB) – that is, how bright the sky itself appears, as opposed to the natural and manmade point sources therein. The authors concluded that light scattered by satellites and space debris had already driven diffuse NSB above the “limiting acceptable value of light pollution at astronomical observatory sites.” According to the researchers’ estimates, the cumulative effect is to increase diffuse light by about 10 percent over natural diffuse NSB; this happens also to be the upper limit set forth by the International Astronomical Union in its standards for observation sites. Nowhere is truly dark, and it’s down to space junk.

Although Kocifaj and coauthors are most worried about the impact on ground-based astronomical observation, it is crucial to note that this level of diffuse NSB is also discernible by the naked eye. In fact, it is perceptible even when individual satellites are not: “Except for the brighter ones, most Earth-orbiting objects cannot be visually detected and tracked individually, since their individual irradiances fall below the visual detection threshold. However, if several such objects are present within the receptive field of a retinal ganglion cell, their combined irradiance may well reach the threshold, and may be perceived as a diffuse skyglow component.” Satellites are brightening our experience of the night sky – and thereby diminishing our ability to see deeper and longer ago into the firmament – even when we don’t realise they’re there.

When existent, SpaceX’s feeble responses have focused on dimming the brightness of the Starlink satellites. Channelling Mick Jagger, the favoured response has been to paint them black. However, it’s unclear (at least to me) whether this will do anything to lessen the major background problem of increasing diffuse NSB. As Kocifaj et al note, “Any piece of matter in Earth orbit illuminated by the Sun reflects or scatters light.” And, in any case, even a complete cessation of the Starlink programme and other megaconstellations will not ameliorate the already dire problem of space-junk-inflicted global light pollution. Only deorbiting existing satellites can do that.

I have set about writing in an attempt to grapple with what’s wrong, fundamentally, with satellite megaconstellations. And perhaps the discussion could rest here: megaconstellations will guarantee that nowhere on Earth is truly dark, worsening an existing problem by orders of magnitude. It is deeply worrying to learn about the contribution of satellites and other space junk to the night sky’s luminosity, especially in light of (so to speak) how ecological deleterious we now understand light pollution to be; see, for example, Dirk Sanders et al’s “A meta-analysis of biological impacts of artificial light at night,” published in Nature: Ecology & Evolution in November 2020, and the numerous footnoted articles in Section 2 of the International Dark-Sky Association’s report “Artificial Light at Night: State of the Science 2022.” (I have also written a series of three short articles covering research on the impact of light pollution on bird migration and other bird behaviours.)

Intuitively, however, satellite megaconstellations were abhorrent even before the publication of the should-be seminal “The proliferation of space objects is a rapidly increasing source of artificial night sky brightness.” Starlink was an atrocity even when we knew only that its gaudy trinkets tried to steal the show from a rare meteor shower in one of Earth’s best stargazing locations. Intuitively, in other words, satellite megaconstellations would be wrong even if background luminosity weren’t an issue. We now know background luminosity is a concern – and quite a major one. In fact, I believe it’s a strong enough worry that it ought to be sufficient to lead to the cessation of the projects. At the same time, however, I don’t believe that it’s necessary for an argument against them, and resting our case here would preempt a deeper dive into the moral problems inherent in littering the night sky with bright shiny satellites. And, thus, onward to §3…

3. A World Without Wilderness

“We need wilderness whether or not we ever set foot in it. We need a refuge even though we may never need to go there. […] We need the possibility of escape as surely as we need hope.” – Edward Abbey, Desert Solitaire

Here is a proposal: what makes satellite megaconstellations bad is that they effectively make it the case that there is no remaining vantage point on Earth where a human observer can see beyond the bounds of the “handiwork” of our own species. We might say, evoking Abbey’s dictum, that in the Starlinked world there will be no wilderness, no refuge, no possibility of escape, no hope.

3.1 A Trammelled and Imprinted Night Sky

The United States’ Wilderness Act of 1964 defines ‘wilderness’ in part as “an area where the earth and its community of life are untrammeled by man,” “retaining its primeval character and influence, without permanent improvements [sic!] or human habitation,” “with the imprint of man’s work substantially unnoticeable.” Satellite megaconstellations impinge on all of these definitive qualities of wilderness. A sky visibly littered with broadband satellites is hardly “primeval” or “untrammeled by man.” Beneath such a sky, the “imprint of man’s work” is substantially noticeable, unavoidable.

On a page about light pollution, the US National Park Service states, “Dark night skies are a wilderness characteristic, a part that cannot be cut out without leaving the land wanting”  (“Night Skies: Wilderness Value”). Of course, this is a critical point when considering the conservation importance of wilderness and the ecological impacts of light pollution; life on the land evolved with regular daily and seasonal cycles of light and dark, and the latter cannot be ignored without leaving the former wanting. But I believe that the NPS is further correct when speaking – as in the present context – about the subjective, experiential value of wilderness to the human spirit. 

The NPS goes on to say, “The opportunity for stepping back in time, removing ourselves from evidence of human development and infrastructure, must include the nighttime hours.” This opportunity is thwarted not only by terrestrial sources of light pollution, as the NPS has in mind, but also by excessively satellit skies. But the NPS lacks the power to regulate the latter, even in the skies above its own parks, and satellite megaconstellations are poised to deprive “the possibility of escape” from everyone, everywhere on Earth.

Other commentators have also stressed the inescapability of satellite megaconstellations. Take, for example, this important line from an International Dark-Sky Association statement on the topic (“Comment in Response to PRM: Update to the Regulations Implementing the Procedural Provisions of the National Environmental Policy Act”): “Unlike conventional sources of light pollution, such as skyglow associated with cities, the view of satellites cannot be evaded simply by traveling to more remote locations. These objects will be visible from everywhere on Earth, except possibly in its extreme polar regions.” 

Krzysztof Stanek, an astronomy professor at Ohio State University (hey, that’s where I work), makes a similar point in a statement to The Atlantic (Marina Koren, “The Night Sky Will Never Be the Same,” Feb 2020): “We can’t opt out. If I get sick and tired of living in Columbus, Ohio, I could move out to a remote cabin and disconnect from the internet. But here, everybody on the entire Earth that ever wants to look at the sky has to look at the Starlink satellites.”

More generally, Starlink, takes away our ability to access any point on the surface (or waters) of Earth from which to escape the intrusion of the works of Man. In so doing, it effectively precludes any vantage point from which we can see beyond the bounds of our own species. We won’t be able to opt out of the technosphere. We won’t have the option to escape into anything that is truly a wilderness. 

3.2 Objections and Limitations

Undoubtedly, satellite megaconstellations will compromise the view of the night sky for people globally, with the result that we will all lose the opportunity to experience the view of nightscape free from artefacts of human contrivance. One still might question, however, whether this is a sufficient or indefeasible reason to halt the launching of satellite megaconstellations. Here are a few types of potential objections:

3.2.1 “Wilderness is a luxury, not a right”

One might question why it is important that humans be able to experience “wilderness values” at all. Sure, witnessing a dark and star-filled sky – in which meteors outshone satellites – was a profound, humbling, and inspiring experience to me. But it doesn’t follow that I or anyone else is entitled to such experiences. My experience, however profound, might be dismissed as a mere luxury. 

This objection is most likely to be delivered by technophiles who believe that “progress” and global internet defeat the supposedly romantic ideal that wilderness ought to exist. This order of priorities is narrow and provincial in its outlook – anthropocentric, Western, and presentist (i.e. failing to reimagine a state of affairs, not so long ago, in which the internet did not exist and therefore was never assumed necessary for happiness, and meanwhile forgetting that the stars have inspired human creativity for millennia). I say more about the internet in §6. More compelling to me, ecocentrists can also hold, for quite different reasons, that human experience of wilderness is a luxury, not a right; I say more about this in §3.2.3.

3.2.2 “Wilderness is already gone; give it up”

One might point out that there are other respects in which we’re already forced to give up on the possibility of genuine wilderness. For example, nowhere on Earth is unaffected by anthropogenic climate change. Thus (the argument goes), it is already impossible to achieve what is allegedly sought, and the goal of pristine “wilderness” must be jettisoned. 

This potential objection is, I think, rather easily dismissed. While it is true that climate change entails that no person or place on Earth is unaffected by the works of humanity, this point seems like a non-starter where the aforementioned wilderness qualities are concerned. The visual effect of satellites is phenomenologically salient and obtrusive in a way that the effects of climate change are not. Extreme weather events have become more common and more extreme in ways that only anthropogenic climate change can explain, but phenomenologically they still present as weather; the human activity that lies behind them does not impress on the senses as do manmade objects or sources of artificial light.

Similar could be said about other sources of pollution that are inescapable yet invisible and inaudible. Even ubiquitous microplastics are, well, micro. And what about that sad fact that existing satellites already prohibit the experience of genuine darkness due to their cumulative effect on sky brightness (§2.3)? It does impact our subjective experience of the night sky, such as by increasing the threshold brightness of the stars we can see even in designated wilderness areas. But sky brightness also varies due to natural causes, such as the moon or auroras, and I don’t believe that this change – even though detectable – overtly impinges on wilderness experience in the same way as a hundred or moving points of light brighter than the brightest stars.

3.2.3 The (prima facie) compelling objection: “Wilderness experience is a human interest; what matters is the interest of wilderness and wildlife themselves”

Finally, one might raise the concern that “wilderness values,” as here presented, are limited to human experience, but the strongest case against satellite megaconstellations ought to be an ecocentric one; they are, after all, a global environmental issue. We already know, moreover, that any human “right” to experience wilderness must be defeasible from an ecocentric perspective. As mentioned in passing in §2.1, humans can “love a wilderness to death,” not only undermining the wilderness characteristics for other human visitors but also – and more damningly – destroying the integrity of the land itself. More fundamental than any human right to experience wilderness is the right of wilderness to human non-interference.

This objection, if compelling, may point in the direction of an even stronger argument against satellite megaconstellations: perhaps the deployment of megaconstellations is wrong because it represents gratuitous human meddling in wild Nature that has a basic right to self-existence and self-determination. So, then, if we are to advance the Wilderness Argument Against Megaconstellations, which version shall we pursue: anthropocentric or ecocentric? 

3.3 Anthropocentric or Ecocentric?

I believe that the ability to experience an unpolluted night sky should be protected as our birthright (see, e.g., the La Palma Declaration, as quoted way back in §0) and that it trumps other purported “rights” like the right to an internet connection (§6). At the same time, I fully concur with the hypothetical critic (i.e. me) that the human right to experience wilderness is defeasible and, specifically, can be overridden by wild Nature’s inherent right to “untrammelled” self-existence. It would cause some discomfort, to say the least, to rest the case against satellite megaconstellations on a matter of human entitlement.

It must be granted, however, that some moral issues just are anthropocentric issues. Breach of contract, for example, is generally morally wrong (ceteris paribus) even if no non-humans are harmed in the process. Racism, sexism, and other discriminatory “-isms” are wrongs internal to the human domain. Rape and murder of fellow humans are wrong irrespective of any effects, or lack thereof, on the more-than-human world. Many more examples could be given, but I presume that it’s a pretty obvious point, even to other diehard ecocentrists. 

To be sure, satellite megaconstellations don’t exist in the same physical space where humans live, work, cheat, lie, discriminate, harass, murder, rape, and enslave one another. But does this physical separation entail that satellite megaconstellations can’t fall under the domain of solely anthropocentric moral concerns? There are numerous other ways in which humans are unique. Only humans, as far as we know, have devised art, music, poetry, myth, and astronomy – all endeavours that might be severely compromised along with the universal despoilment of the Heavens. Some of our non-human kin possess the perceptual faculties to notice the changes in the night sky wrought by satellite megaconstellations, yet they will not be affected in the same way as us psychologically, spiritually, socially, or culturally.

I can imagine that some ecocentrists might attempt this tack in replying to objection 3.2.3: “the ability to experience wilderness – or, more broadly, vantage points from which to witness a world beyond humanity – is instrumentally valuable to the realisation of ecocentric ends, for it promotes humbleness and reverence and respect for Nature; thus, the human right to experience wilderness is an ecocentric matter, albeit indirectly.”

Now, I don’t particularly like the above line of reasoning myself, chiefly because it’s empirically false that a person needs to experience wilderness to adopt ecocentric values, and it’s also empirically false that a person needs to experience a pristine night sky in order to adopt ecocentric values. A person could become an ecocentrist without any experience of either wilderness or natural night. I myself was intuitively ecocentric even when confined to a city, due to a long-standing fascination with the deep-time history of life on Earth, and I was later motivated to become active in conservation following daytime experiences of the more-than-human world in decidedly non-wilderness areas. 

There is another weakness in attempting to force satellite megaconstellations to be an ecocentric issue. Consider one of the pithiest statements of ecocentrism, Aldo Leopold’s land ethic: “A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community. It is wrong when it tends otherwise.” There are two possibilities: either (a) satellite megaconstellations will have an impact on the “integrity, stability, and beauty” of Earth’s biotic communities or (b) they won’t. Either case leads to philosophical issues.

Take first (a). It is quite likely that “integrity, stability, and beauty” of biotic communities will be affected by satellite megaconstellations, due to their impact on non-human celestial navigators (§4.2) and increasing overall levels of light pollution (§2.3). The problem, as I’ve already emphasised, is that the wrongness of launching megaconstellations doesn’t seem to turn on this contingency. Moreover, the wrongness of satellite megaconstellations seem independent of the wrongness of other ecocidal acts behind their creation and deployment, such as the mining of minerals to construct the satellites, the clearing of land for a launch site, the pollution caused by fuels used for the launches, etc. So while it might be that Leopold’s land ethic is sufficient to identify megaconstellations as a moral ill, it doesn’t seem that it is necessary.

Now consider (b). If satellite megaconstellations don’t impact the integrity, stability, and beauty of biotic communities down here on Earth, then in what sense could there be an ecocentric mandate not to deploy them? There are no “biotic communities” 550 km above the Earth’s surface. Should we supplement the land ethic with a “space ethic” that condemns the violation of the integrity, stability, and beauty of regions beyond Earth’s habitable zones? We might consider it. It might look similar to philosopher Stan Godlovitch’s acentric environmental aesthetics (see “Icebreakers: Environmentalism and Natural Aesthetics”). The problem is that this can’t clearly be done merely by extension of the intuitions that underlie the land ethic – which are founded, for Leopold and the many of the rest of us, on our membership in a broader community of life – and an attempt to analogise the land ethic into regions beyond the biosphere would risk losing sight of what is importantly distinct and precious here on our verdant and life-giving planet. 

Indeed, Godlovitch’s own description of acentrism might strike many as a reductio against the view: “Any moral relevance in the distinction between living and non-living is lost in acentrism. Strip-mining the moon becomes morally as problematic as strip-whaling the seas. Nothing distinguishes leaving be Venusian craters or the Amazon rainforest, between active lava flows and the ecology of the Serengeti” (p. 17). I, for one, believe that there is something uniquely important about protecting evolutionary processes in the few places that can sustain them. Protecting the integrity, stability, and beauty of biotic communities on Earth does seem to be a moral demand with a special import that goes beyond any aesthetic imperative to “leave be” planets, stars, or expanses of space (et cetera) that do not, cannot, and near will support life. 

That said, I don’t think we should dismiss “acentrism” entirely. There is, I think, something to be said in favour of adopting a “hands off” policy toward all of the non-human universe, life-giving or not. It has a mark of virtue – a demonstration of an ability to impose and respect limits, to adhere to a default policy of leaving the natural world (and universe) to its own devices rather than meddling needlessly, to keep our dirty hands off of that which doesn’t belong to us. And, here, we begin to make progress to where there’s real potential to reconcile the anthropocentric consequences with the ecocentric intuitions: we need to examine not only the consequences of a sky filled with satellites but also the values and attitudes that have rendered this our planet’s probable fate.

Indeed, I think there is something inherently virtue-theoretic about the intuitions that underlie my slight partial attraction to acentrism. Note that we can’t imagine a strip-mining of the dark side of the moon, for instance, without imagining human actors doing the strip-mining. And those human actors have reasons and motives. Why are they strip-mining the moon? Is it out of greed? Is it some silly sense of competitiveness or the need to prove their power? Is it nothing but the urge to tamper and destroy? It is hard to imagine someone bothering to strip-mine the moon without some perverse motive — the same kind of motives, incidentally, that actually promote ecocide down here on Earth. Even if the goal of the hypothetical lunar mining is to obtain resources for the use of humankind, that presupposes either sheer greed or a failure to manage human overshoot down on Earth; our terrestrial species ought not to depend on the moon for anything more than a beacon and the governance of tides, and any inability to live within our means on Earth presents a gross collective failure. But the point is just this: in any thought experiment in which a person destroys something, there is never just the destruction; there is the person and their reasons for action. And so it is, too, in real-world cases.

4. Techno-Imperialism  

In §3, we examined the conjecture that the basic wrongness of satellite megaconstellations is that they undermine the possibility for the human experience of wilderness values (well, I examined that anyhow; your mileage may vary). In this section, I entertain a different approach to the issue: the deployment of satellite megaconstellations is imperialistic. It is wrong because it imposes the technosphere on others – indeed, on everyone – without their consent or, in most cases, even consultation. Elon Musk and other responsible parties are blameworthy because they dictate for everyone that global high-speed internet access is more important than a natural night sky – despite the fact that it’s quite ludicrous to assume that even all humans (§4.1), let alone all non-humans (§4.2), would share this preference.

The claim here is compatible with the position in §3, but it shifts the locus of attention. Specifically, the primary issue shifts from the consequences of megaconstellations to the attitudes of those responsible for them. According to the former viewpoint, the core problem is an inability to access true wilderness, and the appropriate attitude may be one of grief or mourning at the loss. The present viewpoint, in contrast, might admit that this is a grievous loss, but would refocus attention on the decision makers’ lack of concern or sympathy for those who need the experience of wilderness; the appropriate attitude may be one of moral outrage and indignation directed at human actors. The culpable parties demonstrate a deficit of care or empathy for those affected by their actions, as well as a crude lack of foresight and imagination in considering all of those who might be impacted and what their values and interests might be. By imposing a view of a littered and mechanised night sky upon the entire world, Musk and his enablers exercise a form of cultural imperialism. 

4.1 Respecting Human Values

Perhaps Musk wouldn’t recognise the Big Dipper if it was shoved up his ass. For many, however, the stars and constellations remain an important part of cultural heritage and tradition. Of course we must be careful here: heritage and tradition tend to be quite poor reasons to attempt to justify decisions that impact wild nature (see, e.g., my swift dismal of such rationales in §3.1 of “In Memory of Anholt as I Never Knew Her”). With this caveat, though, it is nonetheless important to be mindful of human cultural diversity: not everyone on Earth fetishises shallow technophilia, and divergent voices demand a hearing. 

4.1.1 “Astrocolonialism” and Indigenous Viewpoints

Recently, there has been some much-needed discussion of the importance of consulting Indigenous people, some of whom have decried satellite megaconstellations as astrocolonialism, as it is described in an article in Vice (Becky Ferreira, 5 Oct 2021, “SpaceX’s Satellite Megaconstellations Are Astrocolonialism, Indigenous Advocates Say”). (See also, e.g., Nikita Amir, 27 Oct 2021, “Light Pollution Threatens Millennia-old Indigenous Navigation Methods,” Discover and Karlie Noon, 20 Apr 2022, “Thousands of satellites are polluting Australian skies, and threatening ancient Indigenous astronomy practices,” The Conversation.)

While I join in condemning the exclusion or underrepresentation of Indigenous voices, I am loath to agree with Ferreira that “Indigenous communities are disproportionately affected by this interference with the night sky.” The night sky ought to be regarded as everyone’s birthright, and megaconstellations are so abhorrent precisely because they deprive everyone of the possibility of reaching a vantage point from which to see beyond the artefacts of humanity and our modern technological society. Presumably, it’s more socially acceptable to argue that marginalised communities will be adversely affected than that the natural night sky is an invaluable source of beauty and inspiration that should be deprived to no one; enchantment in Nature has precious little political purchase, but colonial guilt has some. 

The erasure of Indigenous practices is an important worry, but is it the fundamental worry where megaconstellations are concerned? I think not. For one, appeal to Indigenous culture per se hardly hits ethical bedrock; even when practised by Indigenous people, cultural tradition is not necessarily ethical. Claims of indigenousness cannot right a wrong such as, say, the Faroese Grindadrap (or, in English, “dolphin massacre”) or Aborginal hunting of dugongs in Torres Strait. As a general rule, however, Indigenous cultures have adopted practices that represent a much greater degree of connection with and respect for Nature than the norms of modern Western society, and these include the traditions of celestial navigation, time-keeping, and storytelling that threatened by satellites and light pollution. While not infallible, Indigenous cultures have much more to teach the modern world than Musk and his tech-bro cronies – and reverence for the night sky is one. The loss of the sky is everyone’s loss, but Indigenous communities might generally be better poised to recognise the severity of what is lost, and it is partly for this reason that their consultation is so important: they offer perspectives on the value of the night sky that can and should help all of us to dislodge our own narrowly technocratic and materialistic paradigm.

Erasure of Indigenous cultures may be indirectly relevant in another way. As Nikita Amir points out, “colonial ideas are pervasive in the language we use to describe space. When they’re conceptualized as conquering the ‘final frontier,’ space missions mark yet another chapter in the story of Western expansionism.” Perhaps the same basic attitude of greed and wanton destruction underlies White Man’s conquest of both Earth and Heaven. There is surely something about the attitude of imperialism – its arrogance, destruction, and blind indifference – that deeply offends even irrespective of the harm done. It chauvinistically dismisses other cultures and viewpoints as even potentially valid. This is true even if some Indigenous voices are offered the gesture of nominal consideration. The inclusion of Indigenous perspectives comes with the expectation that these communities will want reliable broadband and, thus, ultimately support the megaconstellations. There is no real attempt to empathetically entertain a difference perspective on technology and Nature.

Astronomers themselves are not necessarily exemplars of virtue when they demand inclusion of Indigenous voices. Since when does the astronomy community care about what Indigenous people regard as sacred? Surely not when it “needs” to build ground-based telescopes! Opposition to satellite megaconstellations may have led to a marriage of convenience between astronomers and Indigenous people, but perhaps no more than that. Here again, there may be a missed opportunity to learn from a worldview that recognises the sacred on Heaven and Earth. One need not appropriate Indigenous myth or religion to be inspired. The natural world – the natural universe – is more than sufficient as source of awe, reverence, and humility, spiritual qualities. We can choose to say of the expanse of the sky, just as we can choose to say of a parcel of land, “Here is a place that our works mustn’t debase and profane.”  

4.1.2 Inherently Unheard Voices

Let us now go further and consider two groups who by their very nature are excluded from the conversation about satellite megaconstellations (the first a rather small one, the second a rather large one): (A) Contactless tribes. (B) The would-be informed perspectives of all humans who, as is, have never had the opportunity to experience a pristine night sky, and thus cannot make an informed judgement.

A. Contactless tribes, by their nature, choose to resist contact with other human communities, including (a) digital communications and (b) consultation with SpaceX executives.

We do not know for sure whether, say, the residents of North Sentinel Island or uncontacted tribes in the Amazon rainforest have any practices or traditions that require a clear and unobstructed view of the starry sky. It is likely, given the prominence of celestial observation in many Indigenous practices throughout the world, but we can’t be certain. We do know, however, that these peoples do not have any practices or traditions that require an internet connection. We don’t need to intrude upon their isolation to gather their opinion on Starlink. Contactless tribes stand to gain nothing from Elon Musk’s pretensions for global high-speed internet. We impose only risk – the threat of losing traditional astronomical knowledge, practices, and customs – with no promise of benefit. 

There may be an even deeper injustice: contactless tribes choose to live in isolation from technological society, a right that even modern Westerners can generally recognise as an important one to respect. But satellite megaconstellations will defile their skies as much as the rest of ours. Such an intrusion might be regarded as violating their chosen isolation, in a way, just as it deprives the rest of us of our wilderness refuge. The defilement of the heavens precludes our retreats to isolation; it precludes their lives in isolation.

B. Individuals who have never had the opportunity to witness a natural night sky – and who now never will – have thereby been denied the ability to form adequately informed judgement on satellite megaconstellations. We will thus never hear what their thoughts and opinions might have been if they had engaged in potentially transformative experiences such as my own night-sky story relayed in §1.1.

Recall the alarming six-year-old statistics from Falchi et al (cited in §2.1): about 60 percent of Europeans and 80 percent of North Americans live(d) in regions in which artificial light renders the sky too bright to see the Milky Way even on the clearest nights. In Singapore, the world’s most light-polluted country, “the entire population lives under skies so bright that the eye cannot fully dark-adapt to night vision.” There was a time even in my own life when I might have uncritically accepted an expansion of internet access over the pristine night sky; I had not yet experienced the profound impact of the star-studded darkness, and thus I simply didn’t think about natural night or its loss. Now I would give up the internet to save the sky, if it were to come down to such a bargain. Had it not been for my own transformative experience, it’s unlikely that I would have ever arrived at this assignment of values. How, then, can we expect others to arrive at an informed valuation for their artificially illuminated armchairs? The megaconstellations will be launched before the majority of Earth’s internet-users will have had a chance to experience a much deeper and more profound type of connectivity – a possibility that we’ll now lose forever.

Today’s children are likely to grow up with no possibility for the awe-inspiring experience of a pristine night sky, and thus little hope of coming to value the night in the manner impressed upon me and many other dark-sky advocates of my own and older generations. If future generations “choose” technology over nature, it is not necessary their own choice at all, but the fate chosen for them by the technocrats of today – a self-fulfilling prophecy implicit in the decision to allow technology to shut out the more-than-human universe and its erstwhile power to overwhelm and inspire. (This point could be made not merely about the night sky.)

4.2 Respecting Non-Human Values

It is almost certain that no (extant) non-human species shares humanity’s aesthetic, spiritual, or scientific interest in the stars. It is also possible that no non-human species are so dependent on celestial navigation that their lifeways would be undone by satellite megaconstellations alone – but here we can be less certain, and it would be just as brazen to presume that no non-humans need a clear view of the stars as to presume that no humans would choose it over a broadband connection. What we do know is that there are non-human species that refer to the stars for navigation.

Celestial navigation has been attributed to species ranging from Harbour Seals (Phoca vitulina) to the Large Yellow Underwing moth (Noctua pronuba). Even the lowly African dung beetle (Scarabaeus satyrus) is famed for its ability to navigate by the stars and the Milky Way “like ancient sailors once did, but without the giant ball of s–t.” Indeed, Scarabaeus satyrus has already been demonstrated to be adversely affected by light pollution; when artificial night sky brightness obscures the beetles’ typical celestial cues, they adopt artificial point sources of light as beacons. Artificial lights are often also associated with artificial surfaces, which dung beetles have a special reason to detest: you can’t bury your poop ball in concrete or asphalt! Orienting toward an artificial light beacon also increases the chances that multiple beetles will meet and come into conflict. It is also bad when African dung beetles find themselves under light-polluted skies with no point sources of light; in this case, they simply become disoriented. (For the studies demonstrating the previous, see Foster et al, 29 July 2021, “Light pollution forces a change in dung beetle orientation behavior,” Cell Biology.)

The impact of satellite megaconstellations on dung beetle orientation has not been tested, to my knowledge, but it would be sheer luck if Scarabaeus satyrus were disoriented in such a way that Elon Musk found himself with thousands of dung balls piled up at his doorstep. 

Let’s now consider a more traditionally beautiful species, and one which is known to become disoriented by false displays of the stars in the night sky: the stunningly gorgeous Indigo Bunting (Passerina cyanea). The migratory propensities of Indigo Buntings are not entirely innate. Young birds learn which way to fly by studying the stars in the night sky.

In the 1960s, a Cornell scientist by the name of Stephen Emlen hand-reared Indigo Buntings for the purpose of deliberately confusing and disorienting them by entrapping them in a planetarium with false displays of the night sky. Specifically, Emlen created a deceptive scene in which the night sky appeared to circle around Betelgeuse instead of Polaris. When time came for autumn migration, the deceived buntings innocently oriented themselves in the wrong direction. In other experiments, mature birds were deliberately confused by being placed in planetariums in which certain stars or constellations were missing. Indigo Buntings could properly orient themselves if Polaris was missing as long as they could see familiar northern constellations. But when these constellations were also removed, the birds lost their way. (Emlen’s results were published in 1970 in Science: “Celestial Rotation: Its Importance in the Development of Migratory Orientation.”)

Now, I should pause here to say that I can’t help but find it ethically problematic to treat Indigo Buntings as mere lab rats – to entrap them in a funnel and deceive them with altered skyscapes, or merely to raise and confine them in a lab at all, rather than allowing them the lives of the wild and free stargazing birds they ought to be. Quite simply, songbirds are not humans, and they cannot give informed consent to research participation in the way that human subjects can; we should, then, err on the side of caution in assuming when an informed bird would fail to give consent. But, hey, this was the 60s, and at least the young birds were not harassed and humiliated by other Indigo Buntings assigned to the role of “planetarium guards,” nor were they made to believe they were administering potentially fatal electric shocks to other buntings who oriented themselves toward the wrong stars. 

(Ethical standards have improved since then, right? Hmm, well, a study published in Nature in 2009 reveals that scientists kidnapped robins from their natural habitat and lesioned their brains to test their ability to navigate using celestial cues. I admit that I didn’t make it past the methodology to read the results; it might be relevant to the present discussion, or it might be mere avian sadism disguised as relevant research.)

If Indigo Buntings and other birds can become disoriented by the alteration of the night sky in planetariums, could they also be disoriented by the alteration of the night sky by thousands of satellites in low-earth orbit? In comments for a Vice article, Emlen himself said, “I do think that will completely screw up birds that are up there at night.” This expert testimony should be enough to halt the launches, if we have any empathy for our feathered friends at all. Perhaps Indigo Buntings and other nocturnal migrants will be able to rely successfully on other cues, like the Earth’s magnetic field, or perhaps they will be able still find their lodestars despite the mess of megaconstellations. But we don’t know that, and there is good reason to doubt it. It is sheer speciesistic arrogance and indifference to fail to pause future launches until the impact on non-human celestial wayfarers can be proven negligible – and stop them entirely if it can’t. 

It might not be too difficult to study: entrap fledgling songbirds, put them in funnels in which they can only look upward, and show them mock-ups of the night sky that simulate its appearance once the sky is fully bloated with the satellite constellations of Starlink and competitors. Or, much better, don’t needlessly stress innocent songbirds who are unable to give informed consent to research participation, and instead apply precautionary thinking: if there is any notable risk that satellites will hamper the navigational abilities of songbirds – and there is – then don’t launch them.

On the night before the fateful launch of the Challenger space shuttle, NASA’s engineers advised their bosses to delay the launch: the temperatures at the launch were too far out of the range of existing data, and there was insufficient evidence to prove that the launch would be safe, and there was good reason to believe that at least one component – the o-rings between the joints of the solid rocket booster – might fail to operate properly. And of course none of us will forget what happened (except possibly the NASA employees responsible for addressing safety concerns during the reentry of the Columbia; they might have forgotten). Where am I going with this? Well, despite my preference for birds over people, I admit that the thought of confused Indigo Buntings doesn’t bring tears to the eyes like recalling the footage of Christa McAuliffe’s students witnessing the shuttle’s “major malfunction”. And I don’t deny that there is a special reason for risk aversion when human lives are in imminent danger. But I contend that an analogous risk-averse principle should also hold in the case of Starlink and other satellite megaconstellations: if there’s insufficient basis to prove the technology safe – for all Earthlings – and good reason for doubt, then don’t launch.

Another analogy is that the moral blameworthiness lies in the knowing and willful exposure of others to an unnecessary degree of risk, merely in an attempt to advantage oneself. Suppose that, by a fluke, the Challenger space shuttle did not combust on launch and indeed completed its entire voyage safely. Given the strength of the concerns voiced by the engineering experts the night before, such a lucky success would hardly exonerate the NASA managers for deciding in favour of the high-risk launch; they would still have knowingly put seven lives at grave risk, merely out of impatience – a crass undervaluing of human life. Now perhaps migratory birds and other non-human celestial wayfarers will get lucky in the face of satellite megaconstellations; perhaps they’ll find other ways to orient themselves in their journeys (whereupon they will perish of other anthropogenic causes such as destruction of habitats and food sources, disruptions of seasonal timings due to climate change, collisions with windows, or predation by feral cats). Even if so, it would not exculpate those who press forward with the launches without even pausing to care.

5. Conclusions?

Let us take stock. Or, well, let me take stock, for this has become quite a rambling essay, and I am beginning to grow impatient to wrap it up and get on with the next one on a new topic. 

The main purpose of this writing has been to take a deep dive into what basic intuitions and moral stances might underlie my visceral opposition to satellite megaconstellations, even though I made clear at the outset what my eventual conclusion would be: “I do suspect that there are root causes to the crises in Heaven and Earth. The disenchantment of humanity. The veneration of the putatively practical. The lack of wonder at – and thus reverence for – Nature as she is in herself” (§0). So where have we been? And what, if anything, is left to say?

5.1 Stock Taking

Here is what is easy to establish: I have been deeply inspired by the experience of the night sky (§1) and believe it’s a tragedy that such a should-be accessible natural wonder is being rapidly cut off from everyone (§2); satellite megaconstellations will be the final death knell for our experience of the natural night sky. But I remain curious exactly where the fundamental wrongdoing lies, and whether it is related (as it feels) to my strong ecocentric leanings.

According to one possible view, what’s fundamentally wrong about satellite megaconstellations is simply that they will deprive all humans from the opportunity to experience true wilderness values anywhere on Earth (§3); as the sun goes down, our viewshed will always be bound by the works of Man. Note that this is an anthropocentric argument, not an ecocentric one, despite the fact that many ecocentrists value the experience of wilderness and that the experience of wilderness can inspire ecocentrism.

According to another possible view, the fundamental wrong isn’t any particular consequence of the satellite megaconstellations (including the deprivation of the wilderness experience) but the attitudes of those who authorise their launches. Specifically, the attitude is one of destructive and imperialistic conquest – one that betrays a lack of genuine concern for the interests and points of view of those who continue to value or rely upon the natural night sky (§4). Some humans (e.g. contactless peoples) and all non-humans clearly have no use for the internet, while they might have use for the star-filled sky; these populations stand only to lose, yet their perspectives are entirely ignored. Here, lack of ecocentric (or biocentric) thought is a subcase, insofar as the potential interests of non-humans are among those ignored (§4.2).

5.2 More on Revealed Attitudes

I think that there’s something to the theses of both §3 and §4 (well, duh, I wouldn’t’ve written them otherwise). But neither goes quite far enough. I believe that §4 may be on the right track in refocusing attention on the attitudes revealed by the willingness to deploy satellite megaconstellations. But I think there is something deeper than the failure to empathetically consider the interests of all relevant stakeholders (whether humans, buntings, dung beetles, or all the rest). The problem, after all, cannot merely be a lack of democratic decision-making, for it seems that there is a correct decision, and that is to choose the glorious wonder of the night sky over the convenience and instant gratification of newfangled digital technologies. The problem isn’t only that the technocrats don’t entertain the idea that other viewpoints and valuations might be valid, but that they themselves are valuing the wrong thing, or valuing it disproportionately. After all, if they deeply and personally understood the human need for the potential of wilderness experience – or the enrapturement of awe and wonder under the natural night sky – then they couldn’t seriously consider going through with the launch of satellite megaconstellations; it wouldn’t be psychologically possible

Arguably, what is most egregious about the launch of Starlink and other such satellites is not what it causes but what it reveals. Hubris. Disenchantment. Shallowness. Complacency. By all rights, civilisation should be aghast. Both literally and idiomatically, the satellites just shouldn’t fly. To accept them as the “unavoidable” result of technological progress is weak and unimaginative. It is to shit upon the human need and longing not merely for the convenient and practical but for the sacred and transcendent, the spiritual and aesthetic, the connection to a world – an entire universe – beyond ourselves. It is to forget or ignore that these experiences must be direct and authentic, unmediated by virtual channels. 

5.3 Whither Ecocentrism?

Here is my standing hypothesis for the connection between my ecocentrism and my viscerally felt repulsion at satellite megaconstellations: the attitudes that a person must hold to countenance megaconstellations are attitudes that cannot be held by an ecocentrist. (Note that this entailment does not run in the opposite direction: an anthropocentrist could hold, for example, that the experience of a natural night sky is a basic human right whereas 5G is not, and thereby also oppose satellite megaconstellations.) 

I am, it should be noted, an ecocentrist of a certain flavour. My ecocentrism is rooted very strongly in a sort of virtue ethics, which valorises such personal qualities as wonder, curiosity, engagement, mindfulness, humility, imagination, empathy, and of course affirmation of the “useless” – a long-standing interest of mine. I believe that ecocentrism is all-but inevitable if one approaches the natural world with an attention that is curious, imaginative, and above all selfless – and this is so whether speaking of direct experience of the natural world or engaged attention to the natural sciences (my own ecocentrism has its deepest roots in book learning: fascination with the lost worlds revealed by palaeontology and cognate disciplines). 

These virtues are lacking in those who believe it’s okay to destroy the night sky for everyone if it means that everyone can have an internet connection. Most grotesque, perhaps, is the entrenched fetishisation of the useful and practical, which is inherent in the presupposition that internet access is a more basic human right than the opportunity to experience wonder, awe, and enchantment in natural night sky, or to the ability to access a place of refuge to immerse oneself in Nature untrammelled by the works of man. 

If the basic sin of those who countenance satellite megaconstellations is disenchantment, the sin of those who develop and deploy them may be hubris. Modesty and humbleness are virtues, and they are virtues that can be instilled by experiences like gazing into a pure night at the staggering depths of the universe, that unfathomable vast space beyond us, without us. We are a species 0.3 million years old on a planet 4,540 million years old in a universe 13,800 million years old. We are one of an untold number of species currently living on Earth, a number likely to be over 10 million. And these 10 million or so species of our own time represent less than one percent of all species to have lived over the past 4 billion years. And our planet is 7.9×103 miles in diameter in a universe about 5.47×1023 miles (93 billion light-years) in diameter. We are small. Yet under a night sky filled with satellites, we will gaze out into the “universe” only to see the consequences of our shallowness, our trivialities and trifles, projected upward broadcast back to our phones, entrenching the cycle of disenchantment. It demands a certain anthropocentric hubris to create such a state of affairs.

5.4 Towards Practical Action? (i.e. Self-Care)

So much for the pretence of objective philosophising. Let’s get back to the real question: where have we gotten as far as my own deep loathing of satellite megaconstellations? What can explain my tendency to be plunged into an abyss of hopelessness and despair whenever I read news about them? Well, I think it comes to just this: if it is my bitter fate to live trapped inside a humanised world, then the least I ask is that those humans share my core values; conversely, if I must lived surrounded by humans with the kind of values and attitudes that make satellite megaconstellations possible, then the least I ask is some vantage point from which I can look beyond this miserable lot and hope and dream. But if humanity allows megaconstellations to continue – as now seems unavoidable – then I am condemned to a life-sentence imprisoned in the same cell as my captors. 

I can forgive humanity its disenchantment only by recalling that, once, I was disenchanted myself, living life in the city and on the screen. It is easy to live day by day in oblivion to the true beauty that exists beyond the cages we’ve built and labelled as progress. I could learn to think of the masses of humanity as not enemies but hapless victims; they were simply never given a proper chance to learn to love the universe, and they were never given a chance to live in a society in which acceptance and survival is not contingent on adoption of the latest technologies sold to us as essential. I could learn to see the masses of humanity as victims rather than perpetrators – but that is nonetheless little consolation. It won’t bring back the sky; the damage there will be done. And whether I’ll be imprisoned with enemies who lack my core values or with hapless victims who lack my core values, I’ll still be imprisoned with a lot of people who lack my core values.

If this is to be the future, then what practical steps can one take? I don’t mean “How can one stop it?” – for though we should protest it, it is far from a foregone conclusion that any of us can stop it, and it is prudent to prepare for the worst. So when I speak of practical steps, I mean “How does one prepare to live with it?” 

I do have a few ideas:

  1. Take pleasure in Nature’s delights during the daytime hours, as a reminder that beauty and wonder still exist. Birds, for one, are not quite extinct yet.
  2. Avoid, as needed, any news publications that focus on space, astronomy, technology, or other sources that might announce further satellite launches; sometimes it breeds only preemptive grief and despair. This strategy helped me immensely these past two years (and not only with respect to satellite megaconstellations).
  3. Connect with other humans who share in the sense of loathing and loss, to understand and support one another. For me, for example, this might be something venting to – or, ideally, with – the IDA Dark Sky Advocate Slack community.Granted, I am not always sure about the advisability of this one. At best, it comes with an important caveat: the attempt to connect with others can backfire when potential allies fail to share the strength of one’s convictions. Even among dark-sky advocates, for example, there are many who think “it’s great that underserved communities can now have broadband” and find themselves in a quandary about satellite megaconstellations rather than a resolute and wholesale rejection. And I would say that most dark-sky advocates lack my deep ecocentric leanings, most ecocentrists don’t count satellite megaconstellations among their main sources of despair, and most modern humans don’t seem to share the strength of my loathing of the cult of usefulness and practicality (perhaps because they themselves are too caught up in it as a means to “earn a living” or save for their retirement on a dead and barren planet under mechanised skies). Connecting with genuinely empathetic humans is wonderful but rare, and the attempt to find them is fraught with danger, for it is often worse to seek empathy and find oneself spurned than to fail to seek it and merely reserve the hope that empathetic humans exist out there. (Well, this “action step” turned dark – and not in the good way. Let’s move on, shall we?)
  4. Remember that satellite megaconstellations aren’t eternal. They will not continue to corrupt the sky for the new species that evolve, or any old ones that reclaim the Earth, after our demise. And even if a remnant of humanity survives (for a while) and grows curious about the stars, they won’t need to actively deorbit Starlink and other satellite constellations. They might require some patience, but those who live for more than a few years post-apocalypse might again see a clear view of the constellations. All currently planned megaconstellations (to my awareness) will be in low-earth orbit, with an operating altitude of about 550 km, and as NASA points out on its page about orbital debris, “Debris left in orbits below 370 miles (600 km) normally fall back to Earth within several years.”

    Admittedly, I don’t like the thought that humanity will leave an enduring blight in the skies, but the real worry as far as persistence are satellites in geostationary orbit (above 36,000 km); space litter at this altitude can stay in orbit indefinitely (see this “handy chart”). But satellites at this altitude can’t be seen by the naked eye – not by us, not by seals or dung beetles or indigo buntings, and presumably not by any new stargazing lifeforms who evolved after we’re gone.
  5. Write the present essay. As I have mentioned elsewhere, I write as personal therapy – to give shape and structure to my own fears and broodings so that I can confront them – not for an audience, not to be read, not to have an impact, not to change the world, not to change the skies above. That is what this piece is.

    If I wanted to transform human attitudes, and thus to change the world, I wouldn’t write. I’m not sure what I would do. Suffice it to say that the true value of the unsullied heavens is that which cannot be stated or argued in words but only experienced and felt. (We could say the same about the intrinsic value of Nature more generally.)

This could be the end of this piece. But I had written more in response to the common “objection” as to why satellite constellations are purportedly worth the loss of the night sky.

6. “But Our Emails!” – Why the “Right” to the Internet is No Excuse

There are no remotely interesting countervailing considerations in favour of satellite megaconstellations. The usual argument given in defence of these monstrosities rests on the premises that (i) everyone needs internet access and (ii) satellite mega-constellations are necessary (or the best way) to make the internet accessible to people around the globe. 

Both premises are false. I will examine each in more detail below. 

TL;DR: Even if we grant that internet access is a good thing to have, that doesn’t entail that the internet must be broadcast to every remote area of Earth (Starlink’s putative selling point), for the simple reason that people shouldn’t be living and working in every remote area of Earth. Once humans decolonise a significant portion (e.g. half) of Earth’s habitable surface, and once humans realise that they don’t need to be online 24-7, then it should be all the more obvious that satellite megaconstellations are a needlessly grandiose means to provide humans with the luxury of internet access. 

6.1 The Internet is Not a Human Right

First, the internet is not a human right. As someone who remembers a world in which personal computers were uncommon and the internet still unimagined by most, I find that a patently ridiculous thing to say. Is the internet f’ing great? Yes. Is it a human right? No. 

As a child, I did have not an internet connection in my life, whether at home, school, Daddy’s office, or the public library. Neither did anyone else I knew. Allegedly, the internet was invented in 1983, but it took well over a decade to make significant inroads into my town. As I recall it, the pre-internet world was not one of mass impoverishment. We had food, shelter, heat, sanitation, and medicine. We were able to communicate, navigate, work, entertain ourselves, tell the time of day, and keep abreast of current affairs (perhaps with more accuracy than in the present era of social media and fake news). And perhaps most notably of all, no one missed or longed for the internet. There was, to be sure, poverty, homelessness, starvation, famine, and numerous other social maladies, but no one would ever have thought to blame such ills on a lack of broadband coverage.

At the same time, some people did stargaze. I mentioned the meteor-viewing parties in the backyard of our five-acre rural lot (with wine coolers and occasionally excitement at a shooting star), but there were surely more serious amateur astronomers as well. And plenty of children had a fascination with outer space. (I was one of them, although my fascination derived more from the experience of reading the National Geographic classic Our Universe than actually looking up at the night sky.) No one in those days missed the internet, as I mentioned, having never had it to begin with, but it’s hard to believe that there wouldn’t’ve been some people – perhaps a lot of people – who would have missed the night sky had it suddenly been yanked away everywhere and indelibly.  

Indeed, for most of history, humankind has drawn wonder, myth, art, poetry, and science from the stars, while knowing nothing of the internet, and hence not regretting its absence. Only in past two or three decades has the baseline has shifted: today, nearly all denizens of the developed world know the internet, but only a small portion have seen the Milky Way or the majority of the once-visible stars. Given this baseline, it is unsurprising that most people believe themselves to carry on just fine without a clear night sky, while they could scarcely imagine life without the internet; it is always much harder to relinquish that which we know. The problem is that this baseline is a historical anomaly – an artefact of this highly non-representative timeslice of human history. It is shortsighted and unimaginative to presume that internet access is more important – even from a purely anthropocentric standpoint – than the ability to gain inspiration, awe, and humility from the star-filled night sky. What if we had surveyed any former generation that knew the stars and the Milky Way but not the internet? 

The internet is an extremely useful tool, but it is ultimately non-essential. We could satisfy our basic survival needs without it; people have been doing that for hundreds of thousands of years, in fact. And some would argue that we can satisfy our social and spiritual needs and desires better without it. Indeed, what would make more sense to me is for a society to guarantee the right to one’s basic needs whether or not one has access to an internet connection. In general, it makes little sense to posit a “human right” to any particular modern technology. It makes much more sense to recognise a human right to opt out of the use of any particular technology (cars, smartphones, internet, etc) – or even to opt out of modern technological society in its entirety – while still being treated with dignity and respect. Participation in modern high-tech society should be non-mandatory, an option at best, not a life sentence imposed on us. I personally find the internet quite useful, and often fun, yet some find it an unwanted distraction or even addiction. Such individuals – indeed, any individuals – should have the right to disconnect. It is our birthright as Earthlings, and as members of the species Homo sapiens, to live in a way that is much simpler, low-tech, and more nature-based than that which technocracy now thrusts upon us. 

This is not the same, mind you, as saying that we as a species must collectively abandon modern technology. That might or might not be true from an ecocentric moral perspective (that’s something I’m still thinking through), and personally there’s quite a lot that I appreciate about modern technology, including the internet. I’d sure like to believe that I can square my internet addiction with my fundamental moral principles. And, as detractors like to point as soon as one begins railing against Starlink, yes, I am posting this from an internet connection.

In light of the above concession, let’s agree that it would be nice to grant everyone on Earth the opportunity to access the internet, even if not strictly speaking a human right. Even then, it doesn’t follow that an internet connection must be always available from all points on Earth (Starlink’s putative selling point). It merely needs to be accessible where people live, and even then not necessarily at everyone’s fingertips 24-7. This should throw into doubt whether megaconstellations are necessary, or even the most reasonable option, to achieve the objective of universal human internet access.

6.2 Universal (Human) Internet Access Doesn’t Require Megaconstellations 

Even if we did declare internet access to be human right, that doesn’t entail that it must be broadcast to every square inch of Earth’s surface. Consider the following:

  • First, 71 percent of Earth’s surface is water. Is it really necessary to be able to access an internet connection on the ocean and seas? No, it is not. There are other ways to navigate and communicate from seafaring vessels, and if you fall overboard, then I’m sorry to say that satellite mega-constellations will do nothing to make your beloved smartphone waterproof.
  • Second, not all of Earth’s land is habitable; one estimate has it that about 15 percent of Earth’s land is uninhabitable. Do people living on uninhabitable land need an internet connection? No, because the land is uninhabitable, so it was a trick question.
  • Third, humans are not the sole inheritors of Earth, and on brute principles of fairness, large portions of the planet’s habitable land ought to be set aside for the self-directed flourishing of natural processes, safeguards of biodiversity, and arenas for the continuation of evolution apart from human influence. Half is a popular percentage here. Given that no other species on Earth uses the internet, there is no reason that the “Half Earth” reserved for Nature needs broadband. Insofar as humans are still permitted to enter as visitors, then they may also use the excursion into wilderness as a time to take a break from their damn text messaging and YouTube cat videos.This brings us down to 12.3 percent of Earth’s surface as candidate grounds for internet coverage.
  • Fourth, consider that even this 12.3 percent of Earth’s surface will not consist entirely of humans sitting at desks (all of whom can be crowded into the state of Texas, as we all know from overpopulation deniers). Much of this land, for instance, would need to be devoted to agriculture. Is an internet connection necessary on every square inch of every farm? Presumably not.
  • Fifth, universal human internet access also doesn’t necessarily require that the internet be accessible to all people at every moment in time. Indeed, as many overworked professionals realise, there indeed is a danger to the normalisation of 24-7 internet access: it also normalises 24-7 availability to employers (or, for that matter, to nosy or overbearing partners, friends, or family members; hell, sometimes I wish I didn’t have 24-7 access to WebMD and other useful tools for self-diagnosing rare lethal diseases based on a single new symptom). Could an adequate version of the “right” to the internet be guaranteed by ensuring, for example, that public libraries or other access points exist and are accessible to all? I don’t think we should rule it out.
  • Finally, even if satellite megaconstellations were determined to be the most effective way to guarantee a right to access the internet within the inhabited 12.3 percent of Earth’s surface, it doesn’t follow that this project should be realised through the work of multiple competing private firms with extremely little regulation or oversight, and no sense at all of caution or respect and deference to Nature. 

I can’t lie: I do enjoy my internet connection quite a lot. I especially cherish being able to work, stay in touch with friends, and remain actively involved in communities of thinkers or advocates, even whilst living as a hermit on a small and remote island. I cherish the boundless access to information as well as the novel sources of comic relief. At the end of the day, however, we don’t genuinely “need” the internet at all – and we certainly don’t need multiple competing companies broadcasting it to every corner of the earth. 

This, then, would be my recommendation going forth. Let us first deal with human overshoot and setting aside space for wild Nature; let us decide which half of Earth to spare, and let us determine how best to share the other half. Meanwhile, let us get on with providing for basic human needs without requiring everyone to have an personal internet connection, smartphone data plan, or other source of 24-7 internet access. Once these ends are met, we can think about how to allocate the luxury of internet access to all humans, including how to do so without harm to wilderness or wild creatures. And if we can’t do the latter, then we should rethink our addiction to the technology. I’m not saying that would be easy. But, seriously, the internet is not the most important thing. 

In Memory of Anholt as I Never Knew Her

Break-up letter for a small island in the Kattegat. Embitterment toward Danish/European conservation objectives. Speculation on potential tensions between consequentialist-oriented conservation goals and “rights of places.” What is it to love a place and what follows therefrom? Aside from heartbreak.

“The present vegetation is a result of human destruction of the original forest ecosystem covering most of Ørkenen and subsequent overexploitation of the organic resources. […] This nature type is of extremely high conservation value, in a Danish as well as in a European context.” – Christensen & Johnsen, “The lichen-rich coastal heath vegetation on the isle of Anholt, Denmark: conservation and management”

“It is inconceivable to me that an ethical relation to land can exist without love, respect, and admiration for land, and a high regard for its value. By value, I of course mean something far broader than mere economic value; I mean value in the philosophical sense.” – Aldo Leopold, A Sand County Almanac

On a remote island in the Kattegat, three hours by boat from the nearest harbour on the mainland, I nearly found a place of belonging. What I got, in the end, was also a rude awakening to a European fascination with the conservation of heathland, despite open recognition that the “habitat type” has derived from anthropogenic deforestation and overexploitation of the land. 

I imagine that European readers might fail to grasp my agitation, and I expect that readers of all nationalities might find my disquisition on the rights of a landscape to be overwrought. But this is how Denmark’s/Europe’s peculiar love affair with wasteland comes off to me, plus some proto-philosophical speculation inspired by subsequent reflection and introspection.

Let me begin, however, by describing the factors behind my initial addiction to Anholt, Denmark’s most remote island, an island I nearly loved – no, an island I loved despite myself.

Vesterlandet, looking toward Ørkenen, with rainbow.

1. In Praise of Anholt: Nothing I Need, Everything I Need

A friend once asked what was in Anholt that attracted me to the island, to which I replied, “Nothing.”

To be sure, one can find not only nothing on the island but also just the right amount of modern amenities. The island features one small central village, Anholt By, with 135 permanent residents or thereabouts. Homes are usually equipped with running water, electricity, internet, and occasionally even indoor showers. There is one grocery store, Dagli’Brugsen, that operates year-round. Even in the winter, Dagli’Brugsen carries a surprisingly good selection of fresh organic produce and other organic items. Its wine selection is even more impressive, and the delicious local Anholt Gin is always in stock.

During the spring, there are more establishments that come alive on the island, but the point I want to stress is that even in the blissfully quiet and solitudinous low season, a visitor needn’t risk starvation (nor sobriety – which, admittedly, is something one might not want to risk once one learns about the island’s history and conservation status).

Anholt is also not as lonely as I’d originally feared, knowing that the island is famed for its vast lichen heath, Ørkenen (The Desert), an anthropogenically created wasteland (see §2). The inhabited portion of the island, the moraine hills of Vesterlandet, is presently home not only to the island’s people but also to more animals, plants, fungi, and landscape variation than I expected. If you know me, then you know that when I say that a place is “not lonely,” what I mean is that it has birds, especially small passerines that flit about my terrace and sing from my rooftop. It was a relief to me to find that Vesterlandet is as birdy as it is (see Appendix A – accidentally deleted but forthcoming?). By typical Danish standards, Vesterlandet is fairly lush at present (i.e. until sun-seeking sommerhus owners eventually succeed in defoliating the entire place again). For that matter, Anholt is probably highly forested by car-free island standards. It must here be emphasised that neither of these two comparisons is saying much of anything. However, given my special affinity for car-free and car-lite islands, this means that giving up on Anholt may still represent a loss to me.

So, then, Anholt has all the basics: heat, hot water, internet, organic veggies, wine, passerines (for now), and a non-zero acreage of wooded land (for now). But what is truly wonderful about Anholt, especially during the off season, is that it has almost nothing other than these basics. It is as if the island became as developed as it needed to be – and then stopped.

One qualification: there are numerous holiday homes that don’t really need to be there, lying silent and unoccupied, nothing but forest clearings. I never counted them, but according to Wikipedia, there are 300-400 of them – over twice the island’s permanent population. Nonetheless, even the holiday homes are much less obtrusive than those in most areas of mainland Denmark (or, for that matter, in most areas full stop). Most significantly, most holiday homes lack a driveway, featuring only an unpaved footpath to the door. There is scarcely any point to waste space on a driveway, given Anholt’s highly attractive feature that only permanent residents can have cars on the island. Furthermore, “natural plots” are more common than turf lawns – if only for the reason that holiday home owners don’t want to spend six hours aboard a ferry on rough seas simply to maintain a lawn.

Vacant holiday homes aside, Anholt in the off-season offers an impressive amount of nothingness. The population is small, and the population density is low (approximately 7.8 people per km^2 – less dense than the state of Idaho, and especially sparse for an inhabited place that is nearly car-free). A very large portion of the island is undeveloped and uncultivated, with over 80 percent “protected” from development of roads, buildings, and even agricultural uses. Sure, it’s protected for entirely wrongheaded and perverse reasons, but suffice it to note for now that this conservation status greatly constrains the potential development of human enterprise on the island – a welcome result as far as it goes. Anholt’s internal development hasn’t expanded to fill more than a fifth of the island’s land – eat your heart out, Nature Needs Half.

There is little light pollution, noise pollution, or air pollution. On all of these fronts, the island is aided considerably not only by its geographic isolation and small population but also by its “car-lite” status. As mentioned previously, cars are permitted only for permanent residents, and even then many permanent residents choose foot or bicycles to navigate tiny Anholt By. Even Dagli’Brugsen, the island’s sole year-round store, offers ample bicycle parking but no car park. The island experiences so little light pollution that it is aspiring to become Denmark’s – and Europe’s – first certified Dark Sky Sanctuary

Stargazing opportunities aside, there is no nightlife on the island, and there is precious little in the way of daylife. Owing to the ferry schedule, there are no daytrippers on Anholt. There are residents, and there are those few guests who willingly endure an often harsh three-hour ferry ride to stay in a place like Anholt in the off season. If one goes to Anholt, one needs a true commitment and desire to go to Anholt in particular, and that requires a special type.

I’m sure the residents are fine too. I admit that I never socialised much. I chose Anholt as a destination without knowing anyone, and everyone knows it’s challenging to make friends as an adult; I will add that it is especially challenging when you live as a hermit on a foreign island where you can’t even accurately reproduce all of the vowel sounds. I mention my human-wise solitude on the island in part as a disclaimer: I can only draw upon my own sentiments toward the land in what follows; I cannot, and do not, purport to speak for local residents themselves

On Anholt in low season one can find nothing to do, and in my time there I never tired of doing it. The winter nights are long beneath some of the darkest skies – and brightest moonlight – I’ve ever experienced. It is the quietest, calmest place I have lived. It is the place I’ve come closest to feeling at home. I loved the island despite myself.

Here’s the rub: as the opening quote indicates, the state in which Anholt is protected is one of extreme human-caused degradation.

View over Ørkenen from Sønderbjerg.

2. Background: Ecocide and Its Veneration

I imagine that most fellow lay people might defer to the expertise of the conservationists and accept that Ørkenen’s present open landscape is something very special and important that must be conserved as it is, and I really do believe there is something to be said for deference to experts. In fact, I believe that it happens far too little these days (COVID-19 and anthropogenic climate change are both real, btw).

Scientific expertise, however, does not always co-occur with principled moral ground, as can be seen frequently in connection with environmental issues, in which good science commonly accompanies nauseating disregard for the intrinsic value of Nature. I won’t deny that lichenologists and other relevant experts might well be correct that Anholt’s present condition delivers something interesting and unique for their field of study, but that doesn’t bestow moral authority on the decision of conservationists to “protect” Anholt in what all agree is a state of extreme human-caused degradation. 

I take a first pass at some relevant moral issues in §3 and (especially) §4. In giving the following brief summary of Anholt’s exploitation, I just invite the reader to suspend deference and be open to the possibility that Anholt’s present conservation objectives really are as f—ed up as they seem on the surface.

And because I can do what I like on this blog and put references anywhere, here are the main references I cite in this section:

Christensen & Johnsen (2001a) The lichen-rich coastal heath vegetation on the isle of Anholt, Denmark — description, history and development, Journal of Coastal Conservation (7), 1-12.

Christensen & Johnsen (2001b) The lichen-rich coastal heath vegetation on the isle of Anholt, Denmark — conservation and management, Journal of Coastal Conservation (7), 13-22. 

2.1 The Rape of Anholt 

As recently as 5000 ybp, most of what is now Anholt was below the sea. After the waters receded, Anholt developed into a forested island, as it remained until the latter half of the 16th century, when humans happened. 

When the first Danish-speaking humans arrived, they gave the creative name “Skoven” (The Forest) to the 19 km^2 lower-lying part of the island today is a (mostly) treeless expanse called “Ørkenen” (The Desert). Records suggest that Scots pine (Pinus sylvestris) was the dominant tree species of Skoven, with oak (Quercus robur) also common.

In 1560, a wood-lit beacon (vippefyr) was built on the island at the order of King Frederik II of Denmark, due to the number of shipwrecks on the reefs surrounding the islands. According to Christensen and Johnsen, as early as 1564 “the king required in a letter the fuel for the beacon to be provided from elsewhere, as the pine forest on Anholt was heavily overcut” (2001a, p 5). However, deforestation continued over subsequent decades, in part due to the islands’ residents “​​ruthlessly cutting the forest for wood tar and for firewood” (ibid), and the forest was finally destroyed during a period of war (against the Swedes) in the early 18th century. Most of the remaining pine stumps were removed a century later. Christensen and Johnsen go on to speculate that, following the deforestation of Anholt, inhabitants “had to change to turf for heating, removing all the organic contents and most of the nutrients of the soil, thereby exposing the sandy subsoil to the wind” (p 6).

TL;DR – “The total clearing of the forest, probably followed by turf cutting, and the heavy exploitation of the vegetation by hay cutting and grazing, resulted in a man-made wasteland” (p 7). Mark that. 

Does this history of devastation imply – as I once thought it might – that Ørkenen might become the subject of conservation efforts aimed at the restoration of native forest? Hmm…

2.2 Redemption Stillborn

Around 1885, reforestation efforts began on Anholt, especially in Vesterlandet, which to this day remains the more interesting portion of the island to those who enjoy the presence of fauna and flora other than lichen (although lichens exist in Vesterlandet too :-o). To be sure, the instigators of these efforts were not worried about habitat loss, biodiversity, or even the profound personal benefits of the company of woodland birds. Instead, their primary motive was to stabilise drift sands, which apparently had developed an annoying tendency to bury the land in the wake of the island’s deforestation and overexploitation.

In 1908, Hermansgave was planted in a 16 hectare portion of Ørkenen. Although this afforestation project was also prompted by the troublesome drift sands, Hermansgave almost sounds like it could’ve been a restoration project, given the choice to plant native Pinus sylvestris and Quercus robur. Nowadays, however, Hermansgave is not regarded as such; instead, it generally just receives slack for the poor growth of the planted trees, before being ignored entirely in favour of the prized open landscape, with no further discussion of its lessons for the reforestation of Anholt (i.e., say, what we could do better to promote the regrowth of native forests beginning with such a depleted landscape).

I might mention, to the plantation’s credit, that one can sometimes actually hear birdsong in the vicinity of Hermansgave, a true rarity in the protected 80 percent of Anholt in Ørkenen. 

And that was about the scope and extent of the stillborn “restoration” of the forest island.

From 1939 onward, Ørkenen has been the subject to a series of conservation ordinances aimed at preserving the “area’s desert-like character,” as it’s put in Overfredningsnævnets afgørelse af 29 august 1980. In 1998 the treeless part of Anholt became protected under the EU’s Natura 2000 programme.

2.3 Because They Are Trees and All Trees Must Die

In Vesterlandet, the non-native Bjergfyr (Pinus mugo) was favoured during the reforestation, perhaps because P. mugo was far and away the most successful tree species at establishing itself in the wasteland. This success would prove fatal – fatal, that is, for many individual trees, which have been aggressively cleared in recent decades, especially in the 1990s. 

I had always been unopposed to the removal of invasive tree species. This is because, prior to Anholt, I had only heard of this in contexts in which the goal was to protect native trees and the rest of the biological communities with which they coevolved. I wasn’t familiar with cases in which invasive trees were persecuted simply because they are TREES and all trees must DIE. Nor is this anything like, say, an ecologically-minded desire to prevent the incursion of forest onto a native grassland ecosystem. Anholt was not naturally a grassland or a desert or a lichen heath but a forest, and a hatred toward the regrowth of trees on an anthropogenically deforested landscape was something entirely novel to me, I must say.  

The motivation for the war against P. mugo on Anholt was never that the invasive was preempting the regeneration of native forests dominated by P. sylvestris. The reason for the fellings is that the incursion of trees – any trees – threatens the integrity of the lichen heath. For example, the Danish conservation organisation Danmarks Naturfredningsforening (DN) states that the growth of pine [“fyr” – so implying either non-native “bjergfyr” or native “skovfyr”?] has prompted conservation action to prevent overgrowth of the open landscape.

And two pages after describing Ørkenen as a “man-made wasteland,” Christensen and Johnsen write of the EU LIFE programme’s clearing self-sown P. mugo trees on the island “due to the high conservation value of the open landscape.” In their follow-up article, after stating that the natural afforestation of Anholt “may well take several hundreds of years,” the authors call P. mugo “a permanent threat to the open heath vegetation” (not, of course, “a permanent threat to the reestablishment of original native flora” or the like), proceeding to recommend, e.g., “If the open heath vegetation is to be maintained, the expansion of Pinus mugo and removal of new growth at regular intervals must be monitored” (2001b, p 20). 

I could give more examples of rhetoric in which Danish conservationists write about clearing foliage from Ørkenen for the sake of protecting the open landscape. But I want to get on to the rest of this post, so just trust me on that. Pinus mugo is hated not because it is non-native but because it is particularly successful in colonising the heathland, and thus it happens to present the biggest threat to Ørkenen’s status as a treeless wasteland – which, as we know, is a landscape of great cultural importance in the Danish and European context.

All conservationists I’ve seen comment on the matter also seem to agree that Ørkenen would revert to Skoven without deliberate tree clearing. Christensen and Johnsen, for example, write that “long-term succession at Anholt is believed to restore a more or less forested ecosystem” (2001b, p 20).

The triumph of Nature against centuries of oppression?

Nah.

Silent wasteland shall remain; afforestation shall not be. Ørkenen shall remain; Skoven shall not be. Thus hath the conservation industry spoken. So let it be written; so let it be done.

2.4 A Load of Bull 

I can’t resist one more comment on Christensen and Johnsen’s recommendations for the “conservation of the present large expanses of lichen heath,” because it serves further to highlight the strange inconsistencies I’ve encountered in my time wishing I could bring myself to support some Danish conservation effort or other: “Should monitoring of the vegetation dynamics show a progressive expansion of the dwarf-shrub heath areas, management by very extensive husbandry grazing should be considered in the future” (2001b, p 21).

Well, I can tell you that at least this has not happened, not yet. I suppose it is only testament to the slowness of the natural successional processes in Ørkenen that Denmark’s ubiquitous practice of grazing cattle in protected areas – another strange fixture of European conservation that I first discovered in Denmark – has not yet found its way to Anholt.

I’m not going to go there, not now. It is my ill fate, it seems, that I must go there soon enough, given that conservation grazing has become entangled with the dominant use of the word ‘rewilding’ in Denmark and Europe more broadly, and that I am meanwhile involved with a soon-to-launch “Rewilding Success Stories” platform (hosted by The Ecological Citizen, everyone’s favourite open-access ecocentric journal). For now, I can only admonish everyone to read the writings of Mark Fisher (Wildland Research Institute, Leeds), who no doubt has done more than anyone to critique the Dutch concept of nature development (natuurontwikkeling) and its subsumption of the so-called “rewilding” movement in Europe. See his contribution to the Rewilding Earth blog, “Drifting from Rewilding” (2019), related ECOS article “Movement ecology and rewilding (2019), and many relevant posts on his website Self-Willed Land.    

No one (to my knowledge) has ever used the term ‘rewilding’ in connection with the anti-afforestation policies that govern Ørkenen on Anholt, but the underlying ideology seems to be cut from the same cloth. Regarding so-called rewilding in mainland Denmark, all I want to say for now is this: the next time a Dane tells you that large herbivore grazing is essential because it replicates the influence that megaherbivores would’ve had in maintaining an open landscape prior to the Pleistocene megafauna extinction (see, e.g., Jens C. Svenning), remember that Anholt was mostly submerged beneath water as recently as 5000 ybp and thereafter became covered by forest, and yet even for Anholt some advise eventual use of conservation grazing to maintain an open landscape. It’s a load of bull.

Lichen, but in Vesterlandet and on a tree

3. Towards a Charitable Interpretation Anholt’s Conservation Status

Look, I don’t mean to piss on lichen. Sure, I have pissed on lichen; it is sometimes a difficult situation to avoid when hiking, especially when hiking on a lichen heath. But I don’t harbour any ill will toward the symbiosis of fungi and algae, and I don’t mean to imply that lichen is not beautiful, scientifically interesting, or ecologically significant, nor that the conservation of rare lichen species is unimportant. So let’s consider the conservation status of Anholt in a somewhat more charitable and nuanced manner. 

First, though, another disclaimer: I’ll be doing proto-philosophy for the rest of this post, not ecology, lichenology, or any other natural science. There will remain gaps that ecologists and other scientific specialists would need to complete for a full diagnosis of Anholt’s situation. I am sketching a set of possibilities in logical space. One benefit of doing so is that the subsequent moral conjectures ought to generalise more broadly than if I were to focus solely on the present realities concerning Anholt.

For example, I am intrigued by the hypothetical possibility that certain endangered species really do depend on the rare habitats found in Ørkenen for their species’ continuation. This is unlikely. More likely, conservationists value the open landscape of the lichen heath as such (“from a cultural, recreational, educational as well as scientific point of view,” as Christensen and Johnsen state) and not because any species-level biodiversity conservation depends on it.

Philosophers, however, can have a tendency to indulge the opposite of the “straw man” fallacy. Maybe we can call it the steel man fallacy (for those down-to-earth practical types who consider all philosophical excursions “fallacious”): construct the strongest possible opponent for the sake of sharpening your philosophical thesis, even if no such strong opponent exists in our real world of irrationality and stupidity. So for part of the following discussion I let myself pretend that Ørkenen is more important for safeguarding (lichen) biodiversity than it probably really is. Doing so helps me to educe my own intuitions about moral bases for protecting wild land, in the context of emotionally significant case study.

Okay, then, back to the motivating question of this section: what, exactly, do conservationists aim to conserve when they protect? Here are two possibilities: (1) the lichen heath ecosystem itself; (2) specific species that have made their homes in Anholt’s lichen heath.

3.1 A Rare Degree of Ecocide Is No Virtue

Is it the lichen health ecosystem itself that’s rare? This is the claim that pervades the actual rhetoric about the importance of conserving Ørkenen. In my view, however, this does nothing but provide a case in point that rarity per se should not equal conservation priority: if the rarity arises from an exceptional degree of human exploitation, then it’s obscene to think that the resultant landscape ought to be preserved on the basis of rarity alone.

Shockingly to me, many conservationists do appear to think in exactly this way, at least when they speak about Ørkenen, and possibly with regard to heathland more generally. For example, immediately before describing its origin in “centuries of human over-exploitation of the original vegetation cover,” Christensen and Johnsen approvingly state, “Large unbroken areas of undisturbed lichen-rich heath vegetation on acidic, nutrient-poor sandy substrate as found in Ørkenen, are rare in present-day Europe” (2001a, 4). So what? Who cares? The end – a rare type of landscape – doesn’t justify the means and, as such, should not be celebrated. 

Some might claim that I am being facile here, that I have made no attempt to understand the complexities and nuances of heath and dune habitats, including the 17 distinct habitat types protected on Anholt under the EU Habitats Directive (see the island’s Natura 2000 page). Well, okay. Perhaps so. But it is not without purpose. I am being deliberately simplistic because I don’t want to lose sight of the overriding concern: the morally appropriateness (or lack thereof) of the fascination with an anthropogenically degraded landscape, regardless of the specifics of its habitat types. 

No doubt that the corpse of a murder victim could provide a habitat for decomposers. As the Australian Museum points out on what looks like an interesting webpage, “A dead body is […] an ecosystem of its own, in which different fauna arrive and depart from the corpse at different times” (“Corpse fauna,” March 2019). In fact, I am quite deeply appalled by our denial of the natural ecology of death in our customs and norms surrounding our treatment of the dead (something for another post, someday). Be that as it may, no matter how deeply one investigates the nuances of the biological processes, one will find nothing that excuses the murder.

Likewise, no matter how scientifically fascinating one finds the ecology of Anholt’s heaths and dunes, one must confront the fact that Ørkenen exists only as a consequence of ecocide. A cold scientific interest in the habitat types found in Ørkenen strikes me as a bit heartless. It is not as chilling as a cold scientific interest in the findings of Nazi medical experiments, but it is something in that direction; if one takes seriously the intrinsic worth of wild nature, then one must question the moral appropriateness of scientific detachment.

Claims of “cultural value” are worse. This justifies nothing. Some also see “cultural value” in shockingly cruel and barbaric practices of hunting small songbirds in Mediterranean countries like Cyprus and southern France. Culture does not excuse barbarity. If a culture values the consequences of anthropogenic deforestation and overexploitation, then that culture needs to change

3.2 Conservation at the Species-Level: A “Thought Experiment”

But perhaps we can offer a more charitable interpretation of Ørkenen’s (alleged) conservation importance. Maybe conservationists speak badly in emphasising the importance of the open landscape per se. Possibly, the protected habitats found in Ørkenen really do provide room and board for members of rare and threatened species. 

I would be considerably more sympathetic to this rationale for the conservation status – if it were true. But we need to ask whether it actually has any merit and, if it does, whether this is sufficient to justify the anti-afforestation agenda. 

First question: is Ørkenen a sanctuary to rare and threatened species? 

Well, it is said to boast around 300 to 400 species of lichens (see, e.g., Dansk Ornitologisk Forening’s page on Anholt) – or approximately one species of lichen for each sommerhus in Vesterlandet. (Those interested in more details about some of the key lichen species can refer to Christensen and Johnsen, 2001a, pp 13ff.) Ørkenen also provides Denmark’s last breeding ground for the Markpiber (Anthus campestris, not to be confused with Mark Piber, Department Head of Naval Engineering at Base Alameda), a passerine that prefers dry open land for its breeding grounds. (See DOF’s blog post “Yngler kun på Anholt: Danmark mister snart to arter ynglefugle,” 10 November 2020.)

Do any species depend on Ørkenen to persist on Earth? If so, that would at least prima facie be a strong reason for protecting Ørkenen as it is. We might rationalise that although Ørkenen is exploitative in its origins, so is digging up the ground to make room for a captive breeding facility or a zoo exhibit. In each case, the end product may be necessary for “the greater good” – sacrificing a piece of land to provide a space in which a critically endangered species can be offered its best chance to make it through a period of mass extinction.

Well, it seems we can rule out Markpiber in support of this justification, since Anthus campestris is a species of least concern globally. It might be a sentimental loss to Denmark if the species were to cease to breed in the country, but the species as a whole would be imperilled if it lost Ørkenen’s present open landscape.  

But what about Ørkenen’s unique flora? What, especially, about those 300-400 species of lichen? Well, as a general matter, I sceptical-by-default of any claim that it is necessary to preserve Ørkenen as such in order to allow the persistence of any particular species. Presumably, the species in question persisted somewhere prior to the destruction of Anholt’s originally forested landscape. Could it not continue to persist there? And if its original natural habitat has been lost, could our restoration efforts not focus on restoring that habitat? Maybe not, but I would like to see the justification written out and scientifically substantiated.

Perhaps the main reason that I am sceptical is that sometimes conservationists do talk about protected species that rely on Anholt, but these are not species of the heath, but the seals that rest on the north tip of the island (see, e.g., the island’s Natura 2000 and Ramsar pages); their coastal habitat could be protected whilst allowing the afforestation of the central part of Ørkenen. 

That said, 300-400 species of lichen is a lot, and this piece is already far too long, and I am still not to the proto-philosophical section that most intrigues me. Thus, rather than research each one and show (most likely) that none of them strictly rely on Ørkenen, I will let my hypothetical opponent have the best possible case: I will assume for the sake of argument that there are rare and threatened lichen species that really do rely on Anholt’s heath. 

Ørkenen in fog

4. Wherein I Engage in Proto-Philosophical Conjecture

Here is the claim that I will advance in this section: it is possible to deny that there is any right to use Anholt as a sacrifice zone even if Ørkenen currently harbours rare lichens or other species that would be threatened by natural afforestation. 

I find this position alluring, not only as one who loved Anholt, but also as a philosopher who is instinctively attracted to those junctures at the nexus of compelling personal sentiment and unexplored gaps in logical space. So what have we here? We have, I think, a very common objection to utilitarian thinking, but where the subject is not a person or even sentient being but an approximately 19 km^2 expanse of land. 

As a reminder, I am not an ethicist (I took moral semantics to get out of the ethics requirement in grad school for philosophy of language), and I am not as well read as I could be even in environmental ethics. Apologies to any who’ve already made the same claims that feel novel to me – and to those who’ve already discredited them – but, then, this is just catharsis for me, never meant for submission to an academic journal.

4.1 Baby Anti-Utilitarianism in Its Macabre Glory

While I adore J.S. Mill’s seminal writings on the steady state economy (see, e.g., The One in Which I Broach Overpopulation), I am hardly one for utilitarianism. Like most non-psychopaths, I share the concern that utilitarianism is flat-out callously inhumane. 

I assume that most readers are familiar with the trolley problem. While I honestly have no idea who’d read this post, many of these hypothetical readers might also already be aware of the “footbridge” variant: intuitively, it’s wrong to push a fat person off a footbridge in front of a runaway trolley, even if doing so would prevent the trolley from hitting and killing five other people chained to the tracks. (Granted, this is a mere thought experiment, and it doesn’t follow that respondents wouldn’t behave otherwise when they are in real-world situations involving shoving obese individuals onto railtracks whereon captives have been chained.) 

Here is another favourite anti-utilitarian thought experiment: is it morally right to seize a healthy person against their will in order to harvest their organs to distribute to persons on the donor list? Intuitive, no, it’s grossly wrong to do that – even if more human lives can be saved as a result of the “donated” organs. In both the “organ donor” thought experiment and the “footbridge” trolley problem variant, pretty much every non-depraved individual has the intuition that it’s wrong to treat a person as an object of sacrifice for the “greater good.”  

Although it’s far from the only possible explanation, there’s a nice Kantian intuition that’s often invoked in explaining counter-utilitarian intuitions in our much beloved macabre thought experiments: it is wrong to treat other human beings as “mere means” – as mere objects of sacrifice – forcibly depriving them of their right, our right, to live as rational, autonomous, self-determined beings. It is wrong to use other people as “mere means to an end,” even when the “end” is saving other human life.

And this is the analogous moral conjecture that Anholt’s Ørkenen has inspired me to consider: it can be wrong to sacrifice an autonomously evolving, self-willed landscape – say, in the form of imposing a deliberately stultifying management regime – even if the purpose is to save endangered species. Even if there’s no real-world issue about saving endangered species (as there probably isn’t), it is worth thinking about the claim, because it serves to highlight the strength of a particular ethical perspective on the rights of land – a perspective that I come to find strangely alluring in my reminiscences about Anholt.

Saving human life is important. So is saving endangered species. No one denies the former in the “footbridge” and “organ donor” thought experiment. And no one needs to deny the latter in my own “thought experiment” concerning Anholt’s conservation status. Ceteris paribus, it is obviously good to prevent a person from dying or a biological species from ceasing to exist. The question is whether the end always justifies the means. When the means involve murdering a healthy person to harvest their organs, the answer is a resounding no. And my proposed analogue is that it can be wrong to sacrifice the autonomy of a natural landscape even when the goal is the preservation of rare species.

Here is another macabre thought experiment (my own this time). First a truth: vultures are obligate scavengers, and they are the most threatened group of birds globally (see, e.g., Buechley and Şekercioğlu, 2016, “The avian scavenger crisis: Looming extinctions, trophic cascades, and loss of critical ecosystem functions”). Now suppose that a mugger fatally wounds your dear Grandma with a knife, and a critically endangered Rüppell’s vulture (Gyps rueppelli) begins circling her immobile body (the specification of the murder weapon is relevant: it would be to the detriment of the scavenger if Grandma had been poisoned or shot with a lead bullet).

Two bystanders, who happen to be conservationists, are overjoyed to see that this member of a highly threatened species is about to enjoy a meal. At that moment, however, Grandma raises her head and gasps, “I’m not quite dead yet!” The onlooking conservationists briefly confer as to whether they ought to attempt to rescue Grandma, but both agree that it is important not to deprive the rare Rüppell’s vulture of her meal. Soon enough, Grandma passes away and the vulture enjoys her supper. 

Now, if you are like most people, and if your grandma is not an evil person, then you would be upset if you learned that bystanders allowed her to die – even if her death resulted in nourishment for a critically endangered obligate scavenger. In my view it is much the same to sacrifice Ørkenen – or, more accurately, to sacrifice Skoven and her capacity for regeneration – to the lichen, even if the lichen are rare, threatened, or endangered. 

Something else I might note here: giving a person a helping hand is not, in itself, an insult to their individual autonomy. If the conservationists in the above example had intervened to save the life of your wounded grandma, then surely they would not have disrespected her personhood; much the opposite. Likewise, ecological restoration conducted with the intent of helping a landscape “be what it wants to be” – such as actively promoting the regeneration of pine forest on Anholt – is not necessarily an affront to the autonomy of the wild landscape. The key difference, I wager, is that it strives to remain respectful to what the land wants, as it were, and merely offers a helping hand to Nature’s own chosen end.

4.2 All You Need Is Love… To Ground a Moral Claim?

I have already alluded to one obvious objection, at least insofar as I invoke the Kantian notion of “rights of persons”: land is not a person. Notably, land is not rational. Land itself does not have the mental capacity of reason. There is an important sense in which a natural landscape can be said to be self-directed and autonomous, but it is of course arational. So then, if not rationality, are there any properties of landscapes that can licence treating them as something analogous to persons in a moral theory? 

Well, here is where I decide to do something possibly heretical: I change the topic. That question we just asked? That’s not how we need to play this game. We can stop looking for properties in the land itself that could “objectively” ground a moral obligation to honour the land’s capacity for autonomy and self-direction. As an alternative, I propose to take seriously the way a human can feel towards the land. What sentiments can we feel that inspire us to respect a landscape in some ways that are analogous to our respect for other human beings?

Let’s try it. Just for fun, let’s try it. After all, all moral philosophy eventually bottoms out in arational, pre-theoretic sentiments. And I believe that it is possible – because I have felt it – that a person can experience feelings of love, compassion, sympathy, and even a sense of reciprocal obligation to an expanse of land. To exclude the moral relevance of such sentiments merely because their object is not a person would be to presuppose anthropocentrism from the outset. So I suggest that we don’t.

When I introspect on my own emotional responses to Anholt’s conservation status, I have been led to a conjecture that I honestly didn’t expect starting out: a personal love of the island compels me to wish to defend the “right” of its undeveloped land to be self-determining, in part due to a desire to “give back” in a reciprocal manner. 

Interestingly to me, this is very different from my “usual” stance on the grounding of the moral imperative to conserve wilderness – viz., roughly, that it is appropriate to feel awe, deference, and respect for the creativity of natural evolutionary, and that enacting this respect requires us to preserve arenas for the continuation thereof – but it more accurately captures the peculiar sense of partial obligation I came to feel with respect to the island of Anholt. I continue to maintain that usual stance, and my intuition is that it ultimately remains more interesting, compelling, and defensible theoretically. However, it is very much a theoretical (and quasi-theological) stance, and as such it fails to capture the very personal elements of the antipathy that I developed towards the rhetoric surrounding the conservation of Ørkenen’s denuded landscape.

I said at the outset that Anholt was an island I loved despite myself, but what do I mean in saying that I “loved” Anholt?

Well, in the first instance, Anholt represents the closest I’ve come to feeling a sense of belonging in a place. So often have I felt that I was born too late in a world too crowded, noisy, busy, bright. This hurried claustrophobic world of skyscrapers, freeways, and motorcars – it gives me nothing I deeply want and it takes so much away. Anholt left space and time for, well, nothing. With the attendant sense of calmness and ease, one is better placed to take note whatever elements of wildness still exist in this place – however depleted – and to begin to dream their potential, the land’s potential to thrive once again. And in developing a sense of belonging, one develops care and compassion in turn; one wants to care for the place one cares for. 

It is not possible to love a person without respecting their individuality and autonomy – that would be something else, perhaps obsession or lust. Genuine love recognises the agency of the beloved; it is not controlling or repressive. So too, I believe, with genuine love for a place, which also can enjoy the capacity to be autonomous, self-directing, and self-governing, and which can also be shown respect by being left the hell alone. 

A loving relationship, moreover, is defined by mutualism and reciprocity. Anholt, of course, owes me nothing. But that makes the feeling all the more profound: Anholt gave freely, without obligation. That being so, I could not bear to live in this place without the ability to give freely in return. And that is where the conservation industry thwarts me. 

If I were to attempt to distill this feeling of reciprocity, I might say this: the island of Anholt gave me a space in which I finally felt like I could come of my own, three hours by boat from the overdeveloped and overpopulated world that so long has suffocated me; I have a strong desire to protect the island’s freedom in turn, her freedom to grow and develop on her own terms, unburdened by the excesses of humanity’s heavy hand. The island herself deserves the opportunity that island once seemed to offer me.

We might here mention the notion of value. Experience of love is a way to come to regard the land as having intrinsic value – “value in the philosophical sense,” as Leopold puts it – not merely economic value, nor merely value “from a cultural, recreational, educational as well as scientific point of view,” which is just another kind of anthropocentric instrumentalization of Nature.

Admittedly, this has hardly been a philosophical argument as to why land can be treated as a person. All I can say is: if you have felt the way that I have felt, you too might accept this position as moral bedrock; it might consume you with disgust to imagine letting the land you love be sacrificed and used as a mere means to an human-decided ends – especially where those ends are mere cultural preferences, but perhaps even if it the human-decided end is to protect certain species at the expense of the land’s own autonomy.

Another disclaimer is that I cannot speak for everyone who might truly and deeply love the land, such as long-term permanent residents who might have an attraction to Anholt that is very different from mine, but quite plausibly a relationship of love nonetheless. Notably, I am not rooted in the tight-knit human community of the island. On the contrary, my perceptions are shaped by my starting point of avoidance of human society – or, at least, its excesses and artificiality. It may only be natural, then, that I project my own drive for freedom from the constrictive forces of modern human societies onto the land herself. Ah, well, I can only say that these are thoughts that Anholt has stirred in me.

I could almost long to live here – this remote island of 80 percent protected lands, this sanctuary of dark skies – where I could thrive in isolation from the worst excesses of the civilised world and its delusion of perpetual growth. But how could I, when the unfairness is so palpable, when the island herself is managed as a monument to humanity’s rapacious plundering and parasitism?

4.3 A Caveat on Partiality

I believe that it is the sense of partial obligation to an island I nearly loved – no, an island I loved despite myself – that explains the strength of my attitude about the conservation objectives for Anholt, as well as its particular flavour. (By partial obligation, I mean the type of special obligation one holds toward a loved one, as opposed to a mere stranger.) 

What I don’t believe, however, is that partiality is necessary to ground the basic moral premise that it can be wrong to sacrifice self-willed land even for “the greater good of the greater number of species.” By analogy, you probably share my intuition that it is wrong to sacrifice anyone to harvest their organs, stop a trolley with their physical mass, or donate their corpse to feed endangered vultures. If the object of sacrifice happens to be a loved one, you might reserve a special hatred to those who decree the sacrificial act, and you might despair in a special powerlessness when you realise that you can do nothing to stop it. But that is tangential to the basic moral intuition: the object of sacrifice doesn’t need to be a loved one to make clear that the imagined action would be wrong

When we speak about forcibly killing people, as philosophers so love to do, it’s obvious that we’re talking about something that’s flat-out wrong to do to anyone. (Okay, sure, there’s always that freshman who raises her hand and says “What if it’s Hilter we push in front of the trolley,” but leaving such complications aside…) In the case of respecting the autonomy of land,  the ultimate moral grounding should be no different, if such a moral obligation exists at all. It should also be an impartial obligation. 

But a big difference, I think, is this: for most of us, our default disposition is one of detachment from any feeling of empathy for the land – even the very landscapes we inhabit and traverse – and with no personal experiences of love and compassion to which to relate, proffered moral absolutes won’t gain a grip.

If we have ever felt love or compassion toward another human being, even just a little bit, it is easy to see the wrong in abusing, manipulating, controlling, or sacrificing a person, and it’s easy then to extrapolate this to strangers. My contention is that it’s possible to come to feel towards a place in a way that is analogous in its ability to reveal moral commitment. The revealed moral commitments may themselves be universal, not partial, but they are revealed through moral sentiments that arise in us through personal experience with specific places.

Maybe this is also why A Sand County Almanac consists almost entirely of Aldo Leopold’s intimate personal observations and anecdotes, and why it thereby works. The classic statement of the land ethic is a universal, impartial principle – “A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community; it is wrong when it tends otherwise” – but the intimacy of Leopold’s own relationship to the land, and the sheer beauty of the words by which he conveys it, is what ultimately makes A Sand County Almanac so compelling.  

I have none of Leopold’s talent as a nature writer, but even if I did, how would I express my love of a place – Skoven – that is not even a memory? I have only these words to offer, a requiem, in memory of Anholt as I never knew her.

Skull in Ørkenen

5. The Antidote to Despair? 

A major takeaway lesson from my time on Anholt is that it is naïve to expect – as I did setting out – that one can participate in ecological restoration anywhere. 

There was a time when I believed that I could choose where to live – or, say, where to stay on extended retreats on tourist visa – based on demographic factors and then engage in conservation and restoration efforts wherever that would be. After all, no matter where one goes in the world, if there’s not nature to conserve, there’s nature to restore, right? With 95 percent of Earth’s land on track to be degraded by 2050, one might think as much.

Early on, Anholt’s desertification even appeared an exciting opportunity – perhaps something like Iceland or the Scottish Highlands – precisely because it was such a degraded landscape with so much need for restoration, however much effort, however much time. LMAO. 

Around the same time that I last left Anholt, disillusioned and demoralised, the Rewilding Earth Podcast released its Episode 90: “The Importance of Ecological Restoration at All Scales” with Bethanie Walder, Executive Director of the Society for Ecological Restoration (SER). It is a good interview, and I encourage all to listen. At the time, however, it was also a punch in the gut. The focus was reforestation, and at several points Walder states that “restoration is the antidote to despair.” Of course, Walder was not addressing me directly, but if she had been, saying “restoration is the antidote to despair” would have been akin to telling an ailing person in a food desert that “healthy eating is key to good health” or a desperately lonely person in quarantine being told that “face-to-face human interaction is the antidote to loneliness.”

The sad fact is that it’s simply not true that an individual can become involved in restoration efforts anywhere in the world, no matter how much restoration is necessary. And what elicits even more despair than a lack of restoration efforts? Why, the presence of anti-restoration efforts, that’s what. I can only assume that Walder has never lived on Anholt. 

Long before my first trip to Anholt, I had already become disillusioned with mainstream environmentalism – its almost exclusive focus on climate change and technological “solutions,” its willful blindness to the ecological destruction caused by its favourite tech solutions, its anthropocentrism, its economization of Nature, its political correctness (including the bizarre popularity of overpopulation denialism), and so forth and so on. Ah, well, I know now that there are yet more enemies from within: protectors of degraded landscapes; enemies of natural regeneration, let alone assisted restoration.

* * *

Sometimes I wonder how our relationship would be – mine and Anholt’s – if I could unknow what I know now. What if I naïvely held to the false belief that Ørkenen was protected for the sake of allowing natural succession, slow as it may be, an long-running observational study of the ability of Nature to reassert herself in the wake of ecocide most foul. Active restoration is nice, but I’ve always had a special affinity for long timescales as well as a trust and respect for Nature’s own creative forces when left the hell alone. It would not be beyond me to respect such a laissez-faire approach to Ørkenen’s eventual reforestation – if that’s what I falsely believed this all to be about. 

What if I never knew the esteem with which conservationists regard the open landscape? What if I never knew the nonchalant disregard of the lichen heath’s destructive origins – the absence of the least intimation of sorrow for the loss of Skoven before? Perhaps in my lifetime everything would look much the same; uninhibited successional processes may take centuries to bring about Anholt’s afforestation. It is the rhetoric of the conservationists that I have come to find so appalling – but perhaps, on the ground, all would look, sound, and smell much the same.

But this is all beside the point, since I can’t unknow the bizarre and eviscerating reality (unless I develop early-onset Alzheimer’s, which I don’t want to do, and for which point I already have, uh, let’s just say alternate plans). It is not enough, in the end, to have nothing. It is not even enough to have nothing in conjunction with organic produce, wine, wifi, and the company of passerines. One would do well also to have hope and a sense of efficacy. One would do well also to have the ability to act upon love. That is what Anholt cannot provide.

And so I take my space and leave only these words, in memory of Anholt as I never knew her.

Kate M, July 2022, off-island

The One in Which I Broach the Topic of Overpopulation

…from the personal to the philosophical, but preciously little by way of the practical, except insofar as the process of creating and sharing such disquisitions is itself a form of palliative medication in the face of inevitable and irreversible ecological deterioration.

…in which topics covered include the following: population ethics at CEHV; the most compelling case for human population reduction is ecocentric or biocentricneglected anthropocentric reasons for human population reductionthe author as a child-free role model?; is ‘the right to procreate’ philosophically interesting?; conservation needs a stronger moral basis than ‘future (human) generations’ rhetoric.

 

The density of population necessary to enable mankind to obtain, in the greatest degree, all the advantages both of co-operation and of social intercourse, has, in all the most populous countries, been attained. A population may be too crowded, though all be amply supplied with food and raiment. It is not good for man to be kept perforce at all times in the presence of his species. A world from which solitude is extirpated, is a very poor ideal. Solitude, in the sense of being often alone, is essential to any depth of meditation or of character; and solitude in the presence of natural beauty and grandeur, is the cradle of thoughts and aspirations which are not only good for the individual, but which society could ill do without. Nor is there much satisfaction in contemplating the world with nothing left to the spontaneous activity of nature; with every rood of land brought into cultivation, which is capable of growing food for human beings; every flowery waste or natural pasture ploughed up, all quadrupeds or birds which are not domesticated for man’s use exterminated as his rivals for food, every hedgerow or superfluous tree rooted out, and scarcely a place left where a wild shrub or flower could grow without being eradicated as a weed in the name of improved agriculture. If the earth must lose that great portion of its pleasantness which it owes to things that the unlimited increase of wealth and population would extirpate from it, for the mere purpose of enabling it to support a larger, but not a better or a happier population, I sincerely hope, for the sake of posterity, that they will be content to be stationary, long before necessity compel them to it. 

– J.S. Mill, “Of the Stationary State” (1848)


Population Ethics at CEHV

I am fortunate that the Ohio State Center for Ethics and Human Values – that’s my employing unit – is not a participant in the politically correct trend of population denial syndrome.

Notably, our former postdoctoral scholar, Trevor Hedberg, spent the part of his postdoc finalising and publishing his book The Environmental Impact of Overpopulation: The Ethics of Procreation. During his time with the Center, Trevor also spoke at an author-meets-critics webinar, which you can watch on YouTube. (I admit that I’ve not read Trevor’s book yet myself, and I know about his views mainly from said webinar and his article for The Ecological Citizen, everyone’s favourite ecocentric peer-reviewed journal, “The Moral Imperative to Reduce Global Population”.)

Our Director, Piers Turner, also recognizes human overpopulation as a problem, although he is sometimes much more hedged than I would be, as in this brief interview with the university’s Sustainability Institute (“The 4 Ws and H of Sustainability Ethics”): ​“It is sometimes said that the ‘Population Bomb’ theory of the ’60s was hyperbolic and wrong. But put into a sustainable development context, where we commit to providing a decent standard of living to 10 or 12 billion people in the future, there’s a version of the theory that may have been right after all.” Granted, in this day and age, I suppose it is bold to bring up overpopulation in such a forum even in a hedged manner.

It’s nice to work in an institutional setting where there’s no pressure to deny that human overpopulation is an ecological catastrophe. But, with that out of the way, let me say that I don’t fully agree with either Hedberg’s or Turner’s approaches to the topic, which are resourcist (i.e. viewing Nature as valuable mainly as a source of resources of practical/survival value) and primarily anthropocentric, even if they each have non-anthropocentric forays.

As usual, I approach matters from the standpoint of a solitary mystic enchanted by Nature. I cannot speak about overpopulation without saying a word on behalf of introverts. First and most importantly, though, I must say a few words on behalf of Nature herself.


Human Overpopulation is Already a Crisis Beyond Measure

It is flatly FALSE that the overpopulation crisis about which Paul Ehrlich and others warned in the 1960s did not come to pass. It has. Human population has exploded, and as a consequence the more-than-human world has suffered beyond measure.

Well, although the full implications are beyond measure, I will still cite a few statistics:

1. Since the “population bomb” explosion that allegedly wasn’t so grim, wildlife populations have been plummeting catastrophically. 

In its 2020 Living Planet Report, the World Wildlife Fund (WWF) reported that, globally, population sizes of wild vertebrates decreased by 68 percent since 1970.

As an avian empath, I would be remiss not also to point out two groundbreaking bird-specific studies. In “Decline of the North American avifauna” (Science, 2019), Rosenberg et al report that the continent has lost 29 percent of its breeding birds since 1970. Two years later, Burns et al published findings that revealed a decline of about 17 to 19 percent in Europe’s breeding bird abundance since only 1980 (“Abundance decline in the avifauna of the European Union reveals cross-continental similarities in biodiversity change,” Ecology and Evolution, 2021).

And these declines are only expected to worsen. Another study published in 2020 found that 85 percent of terrestrial vertebrate species suffer from intense human pressure in at least half of their range (O’Bryan et al, “Intense human pressure is widespread across terrestrial vertebrate ranges,” Global Ecology and Conservation). Estimates suggest that up to one million species are threatened with extinction, primarily as a result of exploitation of land for agriculture and direct exploitation of organisms (see the IPBES 2019 Global Assessment Report on Biodiversity and [offensive term omitted]).

2. Humans and domesticated animals constitute a grossly outsized proportion of total vertebrate biomass.

Today, humans account for about 36 percent of total mammalian biomass. Livestock accounts for about 60 percent (which, of course, exist only to satisfy the desires of the bloated human population; more on my views about livestock in a future post). Meanwhile, wild mammals make up scarcely more than 4 percent of all mammalian biomass. Even in text, that bears repeating: wild mammals make up scarcely more than 4 percent of all mammalian biomass. The same report points out that, indeed, humans and livestock together outweigh all other vertebrates combined, excluding fish (Bar-On et al, “​​The biomass distribution on Earth,” PNAS, 2018). 

While we’re at it, let’s remember those imperilled wild bird populations (I wouldn’t let you forget); Bar-On et al also reveal that the biomass of domestic poultry now exceeds their biomass almost threefold.

I can’t resist citing one more statistic in our discussion of biomass: around the notorious year 2020, human-made mass (e.g. buildings, infrastructure, machines) exceeded the total of all living biomass for the first time in history (Elhacham et al, “Global human-made mass exceeds all living biomass,” Nature, 2020). To repeat: the products of human manufacturing now outweigh all the living biomass on Earth. Now that’s some heavy stuff. (Seriously, though, it’s horrifying.)

3. A grossly disproportionate amount of Earth’s surface has already been usurped to feed all these people.

Overall, agriculture consumes almost half of the Earth’s habitable land, and is it listed as a threat for over 85 percent of the species on the IUCN’s Red List (see, e.g., “Half of the world’s habitable land is used for agriculture” in Our World in Data). According to a 2021 report by the Ramsar Convention (“Global Wetland Outlook”), 35 percent of wetlands have been lost since 1970, primarily due to conversion to agriculture. Agricultural expansion also remains the main driver of deforestation, as UN’s Food and Agriculture Organization states, with 420 million hectares of forest destroyed since 1990. 

To be sure, 77 percent of agricultural land is used for either livestock grazing or the growing of crops for livestock feed (see, again, “Half of the world’s habitable land…”), and there is no reason that the vast majority of people couldn’t adopt a predominantly plant-based diet (I do and it’s yummy). But plant agriculture itself needs to be de-intensified and conducted in a non-ecocidal manner, stripped of pesticides and chemical fertilisers. Aside from this, conversion to plant-based diets risks being just another means of feeding the human population more efficiently, and without an antecedent commitment to create and retain space for Nature, those efficiency gains could result in more human overpopulation rather than more wild creatures and wild land.

There is no need for further justification as to why humanity’s outsized presence on the surface of the Earth is morally reprehensible. It is patently unfair to the millions of other species who have every much claim to their space on this planet as we – or a greater claim, if anything, considering that they were here first. Did we not all learn in kindergarten that it is proper to share?


A Better Anthropocentric Argument against Human Population Growth

If I were to mount an anthropocentric defence of overpopulation-as-a-problem, I wouldn’t go first to resource depletion. I would begin with the more obvious: human overpopulation is arguably the leading cause of the inability to get the eff away from other people. …or, as J.S. Mill rather more delicately stated, “It is not good for man to be kept perforce at all times in the presence of his species. A world from which solitude is extirpated is a very poor ideal.”

In the webinar linked above, Trevor Hedberg states that population growth is not bad in itself. Here I must disagree. After a point, population growth is bad in itself, precisely because by definition it entails an increase in the number of people. Even if such a population were able to continue to meet its material needs and not inflict incurable damage upon the biosphere, too many people in too small a space deprives the individual of sufficient opportunity for quietude and aloneness. As Mill presciently noted, “A population may be too crowded, though all be amply supplied with food and raiment.”

Some might find it callous and out-of-touch that I focus on spiritual benefits of solitude at a time when 690 million people globally are malnourished and overpopulation-driven resource depletion threatens to worsen human suffering. But true to my philosophical tendencies, I happily entertain counterfactual scenarios as useful to ascertain the most basic reasons for a thing. In this case, we can ask, counterfactually, “Could population growth be problematic even if resource depletion were no issue?” And my answer, following Mill, is a resounding yes. This is a point too often missed in discussion of whether it’s possible to feed to the world or to fit everyone inside of the state of Texas. 

Furthermore, although Nature is first and foremost intrinsically valuable, I am also a staunch believer that it should be a basic human right to be able to experience Nature as she exists independently from crowds, infrastructure, agriculture, noise pollution, light pollution, and other anthropogenic intrusions. Such a rich and deep relationship with our Mother Earth ought to be our birthright.

Again, Mill was prophetic: “… Nor is there much satisfaction in contemplating the world with nothing left to the spontaneous activity of nature; with every rood of land brought into cultivation, which is capable of growing food for human beings; every flowery waste or natural pasture ploughed up, all quadrupeds or birds which are not domesticated for man’s use exterminated as his rivals for food, every hedgerow or superfluous tree rooted out, and scarcely a place left where a wild shrub or flower could grow without being eradicated as a weed in the name of improved agriculture.”

I haven’t anything to add to something so perfectly stated, and so relevant after a century and three-quarters.

An Interlude: Changing the Topic

We mustn’t conflate the following two questions: (1) Is overpopulation bad? (2) Is it wrong to pressure people not to reproduce? We will now move from the planetary level to the individual level, from discussion of (1) to discussion in the vicinity of (2).

Whether one starts from the standpoint of ecocentrism, biocentrism, or anthropocentrism, it should be easy to see that there are too many people on Earth. The tricky part is not naming the problem but offering a solution, because all potential solutions raise moral concerns of their own. Telling people to drop dead is out of the question. But, to many people, it is also morally objectionable to tell people that they shouldn’t have children. 

At its heart, overpopulation is an obvious problem with an obvious – and easy – solution: y’all just stop having kids. But few people want to say “y’all just stop having kids.” Heck, I might be one of these spineless individuals, considering that I instead choose to write it on an obscure webpage with no specific audience. 

Most people want to avoid mandatory population controls. Let’s accept this premise, since I don’t have anything specific I want to say about coercion at the moment. So, then, how do we get people to choose voluntarily to stop reproducing? Is it enough to showcase the benefits of a childfree life? Answering this question seems to require some sympathetic understanding of why some people want children in the first place, which I lack (“The Author as Role Model?”). Is there a moral argument that can be used to dissuade would-be parents? On the surface, there seems to be, given our shared responsibility to alleviate the pressures of an overcrowded and excessively human-dominated world. But even here, ostensible tensions arise: we speak of respect for Nature, yet the biosphere as we know it is shaped but nothing if not creatures acting on their naturally-given drive to reproduce (“Population Ethics Should Be Philosophically Interesting, Right?”).

An underlying assumption of both the preferential and moral approaches, as so far described, is the focus on the wants of the would-be parent. But an alternative moral perspective puts the focus on what would be inflicted upon the would-be child. Indeed, especially given today’s planetary crises, I believe that a strong case can be made in favour of antinatalism. 

The Author as Role Model?

I have written much more about material simplicity, downshifting, and car-free living than overpopulation. This is not because I believe that such individual lifestyle choices are more important; on the contrary, I acknowledge that the former will do utterly zilch to “save the planet” in the absence of a significant downsizing of the human population. The bias in my own writing is simply due to the fact that I feel like I actually have something to say about topics like material simplicity, downshifting, and car-free living – specifically, I can attest to the fact that they are liberating – whereas I never really know what to say or do about overpopulation.

On the surface, it might seem that there’s at least one obvious way in which I could positively contribute: I could speak more about my personal life as a happily childfree individual, just as I speak openly about my decisions to downshift and abandon automobile use. In Hedberg’s author-meets-critic session, both Hedberg and commentator Ramona Ilea (Pacific University Oregon) floated the idea of individual contributions to portraying childfree living as a socially acceptable and personally rewarding choice. Ilea asks, “Should everyone try to advertise the advantages of having smaller families?” and “Those of us that are childfree and happy, should we advertise the advantages of having extra time, extra money…?”

Well, it’s true that I’ve voluntarily chosen a childfree life and am exceedingly happy about this. Indeed, I couldn’t imagine life any other way. But there’s the rub: I can’t imagine life any other way. I can’t imagine desiring to have children. I can’t imagine feeling pressure to have children. I can’t so much as imagine entertaining the question of whether to have children. It has never even been a consideration.

Here is a disanalogy. For the past several years, I have had no interest in ever owning or even renting another personal automobile. However, I have owned cars in the past, and I know what it’s like to be enculturated into a society in which the motorist lifestyle is simply taken for granted. When I realised that I don’t actually need a car, it was revelatory and liberatory. In contrast, childlessness has always felt like not only an option but indeed the default option. I didn’t have to experience any revelatory breakthrough to realise that I don’t have to start a family. There was a time when I assumed that having a car was “just something everybody does,” but there was never a time when I assumed that having a child was just something everybody does.

To be sure, I can still vouch for numerous personal and practical benefits of childlessness. Here are some examples: 

  • It saves A LOT of money, making it easier to downshift, take mini-retirements, and otherwise devote less time to paid work and more time to passion work (or leisure, doing nothing, etc.).
  • It provides A LOT more flexibility in both the structuring (or lack thereof) of everyday life and one’s overall life course. It even enables decisions like giving up stable housing and moving around from country to country on tourist visas (not that I am currently doing that or anything). Being childfree makes it generally easier to live without a schedule, plan, or long-term goals. 
  • It makes it A LOT easier to avoid interaction with, or the presence of, children in daily life.

The difficulty for me is that I am psychologically unable to simulate the mindset of wanting to raise a child. Many children are astonishingly noisy, especially considering their small size, and it is invariably awkward to be caught in conversation with a child, even in comparison to being caught in conversation with, say, an engineer or mathematician. I don’t even perceive human babies as especially cute, certainly not in comparison to baby plovers or the little 50mL bottles of scotch or even kittens and puppies. I venerate the process of evolution by natural selection – I think that respect for evolutionary processes needs to lie at the heart of an environmental ethic – and from this perspective I do understand the advantage of an animal’s possessing a drive to reproduce. But I myself am an evolutionary anomaly. 

If I have seldom remarked upon the fact that I don’t have children, that’s because from my point of view it’s just a taken-for-granted background condition, like the fact that I’m not incarcerated or not comatose. My “decision” not to have children was no decision at all; it was merely an action (or an inaction) that flowed automatically from living in accordance with my own nature. When I’m reminded of it, I am happy to speak frankly about the material benefits of childless-ness. However, I can’t speak to how these benefits weigh against whatever it is that people seek when they form a desire to procreate or raise a child.


Population Ethics Should Be Philosophically Interesting, Right?

As someone trained as an analytic philosopher, I get excited about internal tensions and inconsistencies between positions that I find pretheoretically appealing, such as tensions between putative “natural rights” of humans (i.e. rights that humans might be said to enjoy merely in virtue of being Earthlings) and the rights of Nature herself. Usually when I say this, I have in mind something like the (prima facie) right to roam. But we can also think of the “right to procreate” in this context. 

Humans, like all living organisms, have a prima facie right to reproduce. Indeed, on the surface, there’s little that could appear more like an evolution-given “right” than the right to procreate. After all, that’s kinda been the main driver of the evolution and diversification of life since the age of the​​ last eukaryotic common ancestor. 

Respecting the Process of Evolution?

In fact, there’s an even deeper layer here. Philosophically, I find myself compelled by the conjecture that what must ultimately ground an ecocentric ethic is respect for evolutionary processes (I won’t attempt to defend this conjecture here, but it is something that I intend to explore in future posts). But, of course, evolutionary processes have their basis in the drive to reproduce. Take away the desire to mate and produce offspring, and the evolution of life on Earth comes to nothing.

But what would it really mean to respect evolutionary processes? Intuitively, of course, my mind goes to the preservation of large and connected areas of unmanaged land and water, large and genetically diverse populations of wild fauna and flora, and other building blocks of evolution as it unfolds outside of us (see also the Foreman quote in the next section). But this is to ignore the fact that Homo sapiens is itself both a product of and participant in the process of evolution by natural selection. One might thereby argue that, in fact, a genuine respect for evolutionary processes would entail that Homo sapiens ought to wantonly and recklessly reproduce until we hit carrying capacity, since that’s what any species would naturally do, and that’s what drives evolution. On this view, human overpopulation might be considered a natural disturbance that will ultimately create room for novel evolutionary experiments after we crash and burn, according to Nature’s laws. 

True to my nature as more-philosopher-than-activist, I actually find the latter to be a very intriguing position – viscerally appalling, sure, but intellectually intriguing. It would be an interesting exercise to attempt to defend the view and see exactly where it breaks down – if, in fact, it does. I certainly loathe the idea of living on a planet filled to the brim with individuals so heartless and disenchanted that they could accept such an ethical position (it sounds almost as bad as living on Earth in the here and now), but my personal loathing doesn’t necessarily mean that it’s not the conclusion that should follow from my own premises.

Towards Antinatalism

If there’s one thing that does make the putative “right to procreate” philosophically uninteresting, it’s this: even the staunchest ecocentrist won’t deny that we do have moral obligations to individual human beings. Human procreation invariably entails the creation of a human, a moral subject. It is wrong, presumably, to intentionally bring human life in existence when one knows that one is unable adequately to provide for that human’s needs. And it is not hard to argue that, given the level of ecological degradation in today’s world, it is beyond the ability of any would-be parent to meet the needs of any would-be child. For one, the human needs of which J.S. Mill so presciently wrote – the potential for “solitude in the presence of natural beauty and grandeur” and so forth – simply cannot be guaranteed in a world already so degraded and more and more pressed to satisfy even the basic subsistence needs of an outsized human population. 

Some people might not mind living in a crowded “planet of the humans,” devoid of any vestiges of self-willed Nature, and devoid of any animals except ourselves, domesticated species, and perhaps a few enduring friends like cockroaches and bedbugs. But some people would find it fate worse than death. Or worse, say, than extinction. Or worse than never being born. The problem is that we can’t interview would-be children prior to their birth to determine their own preferences. The non-existent cannot give their informed consent to being brought into being, and what right have would-be parents to assume it?

So, then, it would seem that the philosophically boring conclusion is just plain ol’ antinatalism, reviving the classic philosophical work of David Benatar with an injection of ecological reality. According to Benatar, non-existence entails neither pleasure nor pain (duh), and so it’s not bad at all. In contrast, hell, hell is for children, and you know that their little lives can become such a mess… Oh, wait, that’s the wrong Benatar. But the Cape Town philosopher also points out that only existent children (and adults) can suffer pain. (David) Benatar argues, roughly, that because the presence of pain is always bad, but the mere absence of pleasure is not bad in itself (e.g. if someone doesn’t exist to feel it), then on balance it’s always better not to have been born. … or better not to cause someone to come into being.

To add poignancy to Benatar’s abstruse philosophising, I offer this remark from a four-year-old child: “Mom, I don’t want to be alive anymore. … The animals are all going to die, and I don’t want to be here when everything’s dead” (cited in Mary DeMocker, “So Your Kids Are Stressed Out About the Climate Crisis,” which is not an argument for antinatalism, even though that would be a more obvious conclusion and IMHO a more compassionate one).

Everyone accepts that our individual freedoms can be curtailed when they infringe on the rights of other humans, and procreation by definition brings another person into existence – into a world of suffering, degradation, overcrowding, and extinction – and moreover it always does so without that person’s consent. So, philosophically speaking, I think that there’s ultimately a clear, straightforward, uncomplicated conclusion: it’s wrong to procreate. (Easily said, easily done. IMHO. Mileage may vary in real-world conditions.)

Rights of Future Generations? Or Rights to Future Speciation?

Whelp, it should come as no surprise that I have no interest in moral positions based on some notion about what is owed to future human generations. 

Concern for the welfare of future human generations might be good salesmanship to those who’ve already made the decision to reproduce. However, it is simply not adequate as a moral basis for the duty to protect the integrity and autonomy of wild nature.

The Last Man, Revisited

The above point is nothing new. Richard Sylvan made the same point in his well-known Last Man on Earth thought experiment: intuitively, a person is not morally entitled to recklessly destroy plants, animals, and the rest of nature even if that person is the last person on Earth; ergo, our morality must rest on something more than obligations to future humans. Obligations to other humans are insufficient to ground an environmental ethic.

Voluntary childlessness doesn’t add anything new philosophically. It simply transfigures Sylvan’s thought experiment into a form that is not only some philosopher’s thought experiment but eminently relatable. It is not a necessary fact about the world that there will be future human generations. Future generations don’t merely spring into existence. Babies don’t spontaneously manifest out of thin air. The existence of future generations is a choice. It is voluntary. A human body will never produce offspring unless action is taken to enable it. 

To be sure, society can do much more to guarantee that reproduction is a choice. We must oppose the egregious recent decision of the US Supreme Court to deprive women of their right to an abortion. We need better sex ed and access to contraception. We need to combat rape. We need to destigmatize childlessness. In order to take action against them, we need to admit the inadequacies of present societies in permitting reproductive choice – but acknowledging this contingent (and, I hope, changeable) reality doesn’t alter the fact that the existence of future human generations is not a nomological necessity. It is fully consistent with the laws of nature that humans could just stop breeding en masse, rendering it nonsensical to speak of what we owe to our children and grandchildren. 

Voluntary childlessness also highlights another glaring inadequacy with “future generations” rhetoric, and that is to reiterate the antinatalist position of the last section: if you are worried about the welfare of future humans, then don’t bring them into existence. If the welfare of future generations is the matter of concern, there is an option that’s easier and guaranteed more effective than any proposed conservation measure or techno-fix: don’t cause those future humans to come into being

Rights of Future Speciation? 

So, then, what should be our goal as conservationists if not the survival and well-being of future human generations? Well, this is a question that I’m sure to explore again and again. But here is an appealing first-pass. 

I recently relistened to the Rewilding Earth Podcast Episode 1 with Dave Foreman, and (unsurprisingly) Foreman offered a perspective on this question with which I wholeheartedly agree: “I don’t know if Homo sapiens is going to exist in a hundred years the way we’re doing. But what my goal really is, is to have all the building blocks of evolution — which are native species, natural processes, large chunks of land and oceans and lakes and rivers that are off limits to industrial civilization — for whatever comes next, and that’s the greatest legacy we can leave.”

To which I reply, as the kids might say on their social medias, “This.”

These days, it seems, I only find conservation, restoration, or rewilding inspiring from exactly this mindset: we should strive to do as much as we can – however little that might be – to leave the Earth best poised for her productive and creative processes to continue without us, whatever new species may come. 

Any voluntary reduction in population and/or consumption will leave more space to make space for the rest of the species with whom we share this planet. At the end of the day, however, I firmly believe that the only rational and informed option is to relinquish hope that human societies will constrict themselves enough to persist in equilibrium with a flourishing and ever-evolving wild world. The only truly optimistic approach, in my view, is to trust that human extinction eventually will occur – after all, nothing could be more contrary to Nature than for one species to persist forever – and that once finally relieved of this pressure, wild Nature will eventually recover, even if it takes tens of millions of years.

Non-philosophical types will have already immediately dismissed antinatalism and all other moral arguments for extreme population reduction as “unrealistic.” I do not disagree with the charge of unrealism. My disagreement with these folks hinges over whether it is a worthwhile use of time to engage intellectually with unrealistic ideals. I think that it is. It is fun. It is, perhaps, an addiction. I believe that, in a way, it is also a means of coping. In my opinion, it’s insistence on always being practical and down-to-earth that’s a damn boring waste of a life. But I nonetheless do believe that beneath all philosophical flights of fancy, it’s important to retain a sense of what is and is not “realistic.” And what’s realistic is, indeed, that already egregious human overpopulation will continue and worsen.  

False hope is not optimism. Optimism is coming to terms with the likely course of reality and yet still looking for a silver lining, viz., in this case, the renewed evolution of life post-humanity.

There are still many lingering philosophical – and scientific – questions and concerns with Foreman’s appealing construction of our moral duty to rewild Earth. They fascinate me. For now, however, I’ll just mention what is perhaps the largest overarching worry: is there anything that we few ecocentrically-minded humans can actually contribute to leave the Earth in a better position for recovery after the demise of our species? 

Ex hypothesi, none of these contributions will do enough to ward off a large sweeping global extinction event. Why expect, then, that they will do enough to accomplish anything that won’t be a wash in the fullness of geological time? Nature will recover as she will, slowly, on her own terms and in her own time. Dams will collapse on their own. Roads and buildings will crumble to dust. New life will evolve to fill niches left unoccupied by extinction. Perhaps new life will even evolve to metabolise plastic litter and forever chemicals. Could it be anthropocentric arrogance in disguise to suppose that we can bequeath to Nature, in our dying moments, anything that can help the future course of evolution? However we purport to “save the building blocks of evolution,” are we really doing any more than self-care in the face of overwhelming feelings of inefficacy and ecological grief? I would like to think so, and I will continue to explore this alluring moral basis for conservation, but these are concerns that mustn’t be ignored. 

…but, that said, there is also nothing wrong with self-care in the face of overwhelming feelings of inefficacy and ecological grief. 

Palliative Care 

That brings me to one final thought (for now): there is more than one way not to be a complete and utter misanthrope. In the eyes of most people, people who need people, it is inherently misanthropic even to suggest that humans are bound for extinction and that there’s a silver lining in this fact (despite the fact that the very use of phrase ‘silver lining’ ought to make plain that people like myself don’t wish for imminent human extinction but instead consider it generally bad).

IMHO there are other ways to manifest love and care for other humans than to hold out on a false hope that the species will limit its overshoot and live in harmony with the rest of Earth, and there are certainly better ways than to wish upon humanity that fate worse than extinction, that fate of which Mill warned in 1848: a world “from which solitude is extirpated,” a world “with nothing left to the spontaneous activity of nature.” 

In my view, things have already gone far enough down the commode that it’s not unreasonable to change our mindset from life-extension to palliative care: once we admit that things are going to hell and getting worse, what can we do to help others who are coming to terms with this same predicament? What can we do to help others who must endure the destruction of the wild places and wild creatures that they love, powerless to stop the losses? What can we do to help others who find themselves stranded and lost in a world too crowded, too loud, too fast, too mechanised, too sterile, too tame? (Incidentally, here is a moral quandary I sometimes feel when attempting to inspire others to love Nature: it is, in fact, morally wrong to inspire a person to love Nature, knowing that this love is highly likely to lead to a type of grief that this person would otherwise avoid?)    

I raise these questions not to answer them – not here, not now – but to suggest another take on the question of “What should we do about overpopulation?” Overpopulation is here, and worsening, and extremely tough to watch if you’re a human who loves and cares for the more-than-human world. Whatever else we may do to alleviate the strain on the more-than-human world, the mental health of environmental advocates may itself be a concern not worth dismissing out of hand.

 

Kate M., July 2022

Reflections on Downshifting Day

Sunset on dead people

I am the former Associate Director of the Ohio State Center for Ethics and Human Values, a position I held for three years. As of today, I hold the position of Center Associate, a staff position with a lower salary. Even though I made the change voluntarily, at my own request, HR considers this change of position to be a “demotion”.

It is not. The appropriate term for what I have done is downshifting.

Downshifters voluntarily forgo opportunities to maximize their earning potential in order to realize non-monetary benefits, such as having less job-related stress, enjoying more leisure time, engaging in work that it personally more rewarding but less lucrative, or so on. I heartily recommend it!

Here is a sort of advice column I wrote back in 2018 on the topic:

You’re Going to Die (Plus Some Less Conventional Advice)

Even though my personal goals and areas of focus have changed in some major ways since 2018, I find that I very much still agree with the bulk and substance of it.

I am no stranger to downshifting. This is the fourth or so time I’ve engaged in downshifting-type behavior.

The main impetus this time around was, to put it somewhat vaguely, to free myself from a certain job responsibility that I found particularly mentally and emotionally draining. In doing so, I greatly increase the time, energy, stamina, and enthusiasm that I can devote to passion projects, especially my current interest in ecocentric ethics and related topics (I would say “rewilding” but what a semantic clusterf–k — that’s a technical term for a cluster concept confounded to the point of uselessness — I’m discovering that term to be). As a reminder: as always, my job ≠ my passion, just a reasonably pleasant way to earn an income and stay engaged with some colleagues whom I think are fine human beings. And so do I prefer it.

Celebratory Dinner with Ammonite and BennuBird.

Here are some previous examples of downshifting-type behavior:

1. Switching from a PhD program in Statistics to one in Philosophy (leaving Statistics with a terminal Masters). I had good standing in the Statistics program, but I had come to realize that I had considerably more passion for the discipline and methodology of philosophy — or, perhaps better put, simply an irresistible urge to complete a doctorate in the discipline. Some people might consider a “downshift” because the expected future earnings of philosophers is much lower than that of statisticians. For me, the downshifting element simply had to do with the fact that Philosophy graduate students were paid less than Statistics graduate students. I never thought in terms of future careers, not even as a graduate student; I was there for the intrinsic pleasure of exercising my cognitive faculties.

2. Turning down a reasonably well-paying job, which I’d previously thought I wanted, and instead choosing to sell my labor only part-time so that I could concentrate on volunteer work. This happened in mid-2016, when I was in the process of becoming “famous” in the basic income world as the lead writer for Basic Income News, to which I was contributing on nearly a daily basis as a volunteer. I worked considerably more hours for the basic income movement in those days than I did to earn my own “basic income”.

3. Withdrawing from the basic income world, and the potential for further paid opportunities therein, when I’d eventually had enough (after some eventual unexpected financial success). I won’t elaborate reasons I won’t elaborate here; it was partly profound disillusionment with the movement, but partly sheer boredom with the narrow focus and a desire to learn something new, to challenge myself in a new domain. At this time, I took an all-out mini retirement to provide myself with space to find out what new passions, interests, and opportunities would find me, and it was in this context that I wrote the above-linked “You’re Going to Die” article.

As an undergraduate, I changed my major fairly frequently, even though I threw myself entirely to whatever I’d chosen for a given term. No one directly criticized me for my fickleness, but I was aware of the appearance. I remember writing on one of my folders (as undergraduates are prone to do): “Some may say I drift in my goals, but my goal is to be a drifter.” I stand by that sentiment still today. Life is too short and the universe too vast to live and die as some kind of career specialist.

Kate M., Center Associate, 1 July 2022