Speculations about Equal Protection: The Difficulties of Principled Line-Drawing

As Coleman v. Franken moves to the Minnesota Supreme Court, the law professor in me continues to ponder the constitutional question that is the heart of Coleman’s appeal. In this essay, I neither repeat nor recant what I wrote last week about the Minnesota trial court’s decision. Instead, I wish to explore why I remain uneasy about the Equal Protection issue in the case, despite what the three trial judges unanimously—and rather cogently—wrote about the issue.

I hasten to say that the outset that my unease does not translate automatically into a belief that Coleman has a meritorious Equal Protection claim on appeal (and thus even less implies that Coleman’s appeal, if meritorious as to the law of Equal Protection, translates into enough new votes to overcome Franken’s 312-vote victory, as pronounced by the trial court). But this unease does suggest that I, for one, am still searching for the clearly discernible principle that explains why Bush v. Gore presented a valid Equal Protection claim but Coleman v. Franken does not.

(The exercise on which I am about to embark assumes that it is worthwhile to search for principled understanding of Bush v. Gore and its applicability as precedent to future cases. Some scholars and perhaps lower-court judges, too, have doubts on this point. But I take it as a basic precept of our judicial system that, unless and until Bush v. Gore is overruled or narrowed by the U.S. Supreme Court itself, it is the obligation of lower-court judges to accept its authoritative status and thus attempt to treat it in a principled way, as they would any other Supreme Court precedent. In any event, I proceed on that assumption, as I have elsewhere).

In distinguishing Bush v. Gore, the three judges relied heavily, as they have before, on the fact that Minnesota’s statutes are quite precise on the limited permissible grounds for rejecting an absentee ballot, whereas Florida law was notoriously vague on how to handle a dimpled or hanging chad. But that distinction between Minnesota and Florida can’t completely explain away the precedent of Bush v. Gore. To understand this point, consider the following hypothetical.

Helpful Hypotheticals?

Suppose that the State of Utopia (a favorite on law school exams) has a statute providing that an absentee ballot cannot count unless the voter’s address is “complete” on the envelope in which the ballot is submitted. That statute would seem to provide the clarity contemplated by the Minnesota trial court’s opinion. But suppose that the Utopia Supreme Court had interpreted this statute to mean that an address on an envelope is adequately “complete” even if it is missing a zip code or other piece of information, as long as the relevant local board of election considers the information provided to be sufficient to identify the voter.

Suppose, further, that local boards then differ on how much of an address can be missing and still be adequately “complete” under the Utopia Supreme Court’s overarching standard. Some local boards will permit both the zip code and town name to be missing, as long as they can recognize the street address as being within their jurisdiction, whereas other boards do not consider a street address alone to be sufficient, but will require either the zip code or town name to complete the voter’s address.

This hypothetical situation now seems comparable to Bush v. Gore despite the apparent clarity of Utopia’s statute. Indeed, the problem in Bush v. Gore was not the vagueness of language in Florida’s statutes. On the contrary, as Chief Justice Rehnquist wrote in his concurrence, Florida’s statutes did not contemplate any statewide manual recount of chads that voters failed to dislodge completely. (531 U.S. at 118-119.) Instead, the problem in Bush v. Gore was vagueness in Florida law generated by the Florida Supreme Court’s decision to permit the statewide manual recounting of less-than-completely-dislodged chads according to a general “intent of the voter” standard. As a result, some Florida localities would accept a dimpled chad as a valid vote, while others would require a chad to be punctured, with light passing through, in order to count it. This locally different treatment of equivalent chads, caused by the Florida Supreme Court’s imprecision, seems no different in principle than the locally different treatment of equivalent addresses on absentee ballot envelopes caused by the Utopia Supreme Court’s imprecision.

What the Florida, or Utopia, statute says does not change the situation. As the majority opinion in Bush v. Gore explained:

“For the purposes of resolving the equal protection challenge, it is not necessary to decide whether the Florida Supreme Court had the authority under the legislative scheme for resolving election disputes to define what a legal vote is and to mandate a manual recount implementing that definition.” (531 U.S. at 105.)

The local variation caused by the Florida Supreme Court’s imprecision was enough to create the Equal Protection problem in Bush v. Gore, regardless of what the Florida statute provided. The same point is true about the hypothetical Utopia Supreme Court’s interpretative gloss that clouds the preexisting precision in Utopia’s statute.

Now, someone may accept this point about the Utopia hypothetical, as far as it goes, but say that it is irrelevant to the real-world comparison between Bush v. Gore and Coleman v. Franken. The Minnesota Supreme Court has not construed the state’s absentee ballots statutes to render them imprecise in the same way as the Utopia Supreme Court. (Coleman may argue that the Minnesota Supreme Court’s 3-2 ruling, which required previously rejected absentee ballots to count, if both Coleman and Franken—along with the local election officials—agree that they had been wrongly rejected, added an element of imprecision that did not previously exist in the statute. Maybe so, but Coleman was not required to agree to the counting of any absentee ballots he thought would create an Equal Protection problem, and so it would seem that he should be precluded from complaining now about this particular judicial ruling.)

Let us, then, modify the Utopia hypothetical to say that the Utopia Secretary of State, rather than the Utopia Supreme Court, is the authority responsible for interpreting the statute in a way that introduces imprecision. To be sure, there are those who say that it is crucial to understanding the Equal Protection holding in Bush v. Gore that Florida’s judiciary was responsible for the imprecise standard that governed the court-ordered statewide recount. We’ll never know for certain unless and until the U.S. Supreme Court clarifies the imprecision of Bush v. Gore itself, but I for one believe that the Bush v. Gore Court would have found the same Equal Protection violation if the local variation in treatment of dimpled chads had been caused by an order for a statewide recount issued by the Florida Secretary of State. After all, for the Secretary of State’s imprecise standard to be operational, the state’s judiciary would have to acquiesce in it. Thus, it would seem to matter little for purposes of Equal Protection analysis whether the imprecision in state law was caused by the Florida judiciary directly or by the Florida judiciary upholding an equivalent order from the Secretary of State.

Still, the relevance of the modified Utopia hypothetical may be questioned, since there is no claim (of which I am aware) that the Minnesota Secretary of State has issued an order causing Minnesota’s statute regarding absentee ballots to become imprecise. But is an order from the Secretary of State really necessary for the equivalent situation to exist under Equal Protection analysis? Making another modification to the Utopia hypothetical, suppose that local boards of election take it upon themselves to interpret in different ways what the statute means by a “complete” address. Some counties on their own decide to accept an address without either a town name or zip code, while other counties insist on at least one or the either. If neither the Utopia Secretary of State nor the Utopia Supreme Court invalidates that local variation in the interpretation of the state statute, isn’t that situation essentially the same as if the Utopia Secretary or State or Utopia Supreme Court issued a ruling that caused the identical local variation? (Presumably, either the Utopia Secretary of State or the Utopia Supreme Court, or both, will have the opportunity to pass judgment on the validity of the varied local interpretations of the relevant state statute in the event that a close election becomes disputed and enters some sort of administrative recount and/or judicial contest to review the result.) Would it have made a difference in Bush v. Gore if Florida had required an automatic manual statewide recount, given the closeness of the vote between Bush and Gore, but then the localities on their own developed different standards for handling dimpled chads? If in response to this local variation the Florida Supreme Court had not insisted on statewide uniformity with respect to identically dimpled ballots, would not the Bush v. Gore majority have found the same Equal Protection violation?

Counting or Recounting Ballots: Does “Equal Protection” Apply Differently?

Most of Minnesota’s real-world variation in the treatment of absentee ballots occurred during the initial counting and canvassing of the ballots, before the recount and subsequent Coleman v. Franken trial occurred. Perhaps this fact is the key to understanding the difference between Coleman v. Franken and Bush v. Gore. (Rick Hasen and Eric Black have suggested that it might be.) Interpretative gloss that renders a statute imprecise, if it occurs before there is an initial count of ballots showing a miniscule margin of victory, cannot be viewed as a suspicious effort to distort the plain meaning of a vote-counting statute in order to skew the result towards a favored candidate. There is at least a hint of this concern in the U.S. Supreme Court’s majority opinion in Bush v. Gore. The opinion’s description of the facts in Bush v. Gore gives the impression that the Court’s majority is troubled by what it perceives to be the unstable, chaotic, and thus arbitrary procedures that result from the apparently novel interpretative gloss on Florida’s statutes that emerges in the midst of this intense vote-counting dispute: “three members of the [same] county canvassing board applied different standards in defining a legal vote”; “at least one county changed its evaluative standards during the counting process”; and so forth. This variation in the rules for counting ballots occurred all while the vote-counters knew the exceedingly narrow gap in the then-pending vote totals for Bush and Gore.

By contrast, when local officials in Minnesota varied in their initial decision to accept or reject absentee ballots, they did not know whether Coleman or Franken (or even Barkley) would be ahead, or by how many votes. But if this distinction best explains the difference between Coleman v. Franken and Bush v. Gore, it is intellectually frustrating that the three-judge trial court’s opinion did not explicitly rely on it. Yet if the court had replied on it, would this distinction have held up under rigorous analysis? Even though the interpretative gloss that causes statutory imprecision occurs before a recount in a razor-thin election, if the recount process validates the vote totals that result from that interpretative gloss—rather than insisting that a strict reading of the statute govern all of the ballots cast in the election—then isn’t that post-hoc validation of the interpretive gloss essentially the same as when the interpretative gloss itself surfaces after the ballots were cast?

If the local variation in dimpled chads had occurred because the interpretative gloss on Florida’s statutes was longstanding, as some argued at the time, would the venerability of the interpretive imprecision have made a difference to the Bush v. Gore majority? After all, the Florida Supreme Court ratified that local variation regardless of the pedigree of the interpretative gloss. Does when the interpretative gloss first occurred really matter, assuming that the interpretative gloss eventually controls which ballots count and which don’t?

The three-judge trial court opinion in Minnesota, in its effort to distinguish Bush v. Gore, says that it adhered to a strict understanding of the relevant statute. In doing so, it seemed to disavow any ratification on any interpretative gloss by local election boards that may have caused imprecision, and thus variation, in the counting of absentee ballots. But the three-judge court’s decision leaves standing the local decisions made in accordance with their own interpretative gloss and, in that sense, is a ratification of those decisions (even though the court itself would not have made these ballot-by-ballot decisions in the same way).

The Relationship of Right and Remedy?

The three-judge court makes the further remedial point that it cannot undo the counting of absentee ballots already counted. Yet it makes this point as a matter of state law, not federal Equal Protection. It remains unclear what role this remedial point should have in Equal Protection analysis.

Suppose that in the State of Utopia it is physically possible to uncount absentee ballots that had already been counted in localities that adopted a more lenient view of what qualifies as a “complete” address. It would also be possible, of course, to count absentee ballots that had been rejected in localities that had adopted the stricter “complete” address standard. In this situation, according to conventional federal Equal Protection analysis, the remedial question of whether to uncount some, or count others, would be detached from the underlying question of whether equivalent ballots must be treated the same in different localities. Assuming that the correct answer to this federal Equal Protection question is yes—two ballots with equivalent completeness of their addresses must either both be counted or both be rejected, regardless of the locality in which they were cast—then, as long as this federal Equal Protection requirement were satisfied, federal law would leave it to state law to decide whether remedially to count both or reject both.

Utopia, however, could not avoid the federal obligation of equal treatment by asserting that under state law it did not want to uncount previously counted ballots. Fine, federal law would say, exercise your other option by making uniform the more lenient interpretative gloss. “We don’t want to do that either,” Utopia might say. “Too bad,” is the federal response. Provide equality one way or the other, but what you can’t do is deny equality.

The real-world question in Coleman v. Franken is whether this conventional Equal Protection relationship between federal-law right and state-law remedy changes if one of the two remedial alternatives is physically impossible. Federal law might say, in effect, to the state: that’s your problem; as long as you provide equality, we don’t care remedially how you do it; but you can’t claim avoidance of the federal equality obligation by saying that one of two remedial options is unavailable. But maybe the remedial constraint facing Minnesota in Coleman v. Franken should factor into Equal Protection analysis under Bush v. Gore in a way the departs from conventional Equal Protection analysis. If so, the three-judge panel’s opinion did not supply the justification for that departure.

Resource Inequalities to Justify Electoral Inequalities?

In their opinion, the three trial judges in Coleman v. Franken observed that Bush v. Gore indisputably accepts some local variation in the administration of a state’s electoral processes. The three judges further observed that Bush v. Gore seems especially tolerant of local variation caused by differences in available resources among localities for operating the voting process. Some kinds of voting equipment, for example, are more expensive than other kinds, and the U.S. Supreme Court went out of its way to acknowledge that the decision to purchase less expensive voting equipment did not necessarily violate Equal Protection even if inferior equipment results in fewer votes accurately counted in those localities. The three trial judges in Coleman v. Franken grabbed onto that acknowledgement in Bush v. Gore and reasoned that differences in available resources could explain some (and perhaps most) of the local variation among Minnesota counties in the treatment of absentee ballots.

The problem with this “differential resources” argument is that it makes sense when a state’s legislature clearly contemplates local authority to make different decisions based on variations in available resources. It does not make sense in a situation where the state legislature, by statute, has mandated a single statewide standard, but the localities have taken it upon themselves to make different resource-based choices. As I have indicated in some of my scholarship on Bush v. Gore, it is difficult to say that the unequal treatment of identical ballots is “rationally related to a legitimate state interest” in promoting local control over the allocation of scarce resources, when the state’s legislature already has demanded uniformity in the particular context.

“The state-wide standards governing absentee voting in Minnesota are uniform and explicit and apply in every county and city in the state.”  That’s what the three judges said in their final ruling. But given this, it would seem difficult to apply the “differential resources” argument in this context. Even if some localities have much fewer resources than others, the less affluent localities shouldn’t be deviating from legislative mandate for statewide uniformity with respect to counting absentee ballots. In other words, the “differential resources” argument is a good one in some situations, but here it seems in considerable tension with the trial court’s other arguments concerning the clarity and strictness of the state’s applicable statutes.

Local Mistakes Differ from Local Policies

There remains the matter of mistakes. It is possible that some variation among Minnesota counties is caused simply by administrative errors in the implementation of clear statutory directives. I agree with the trial court in Coleman v. Franken insofar as it opines that sporadic good-faith administrative errors, evincing no bias towards any candidate or party, do not rise to the level of a constitutional violation, and Bush v. Gore does not require otherwise.

If the record in a case shows a clear state statute, and if the only deviations from the requirements of that clear state statute are caused by essentially random administrative errors, then Bush v. Gore is distinguishable because there has been no policy-based interpretative gloss that has rendered the statutory standard imprecise. Not from the State Supreme Court. Not from the Secretary of State. And not even from the local jurisdictions themselves acting in accordance with their own policy-based interpretations of the state statute. Instead, just mistakes, pure and simple.

But this distinction between local mistake and local policy is one that deserved more attention from the trial court. As I suggested in an essay midway through the trial, this distinction ultimately might be the one that best separates tenable from untenable Equal Protection claims. In its final ruling, however, the trial court did not attempt to reject the entirety of Coleman’s Equal Protection claim by asserting that all the demonstrated variation among localities in the treatment of absentee ballots was explicable on grounds of local errors rather than local policy. Perhaps the evidence would not have supported that approach. But the trial court’s opinion thus leaves the impression that at least some of the variation among Minnesota counties in the treatment of absentee ballots is caused by differences in consciously adopted local policies, rather than local mistakes. Yet it is the apparent existence of policy-based local differences in the treatment of identical ballots, despite the asserted clarity and strictness of the uniformly applicable state statute for the counting of these ballots, that gives rise to the uneasy feeling that Coleman v. Franken is not as readily distinguishable from Bush v. Gore as the trial court maintained. If Minnesota localities were adopting different interpretive glosses on the relevant statute, rendering it less precise than written, why was the state judiciary tolerating this interpretative deviation, and is this judicial toleration of local interpretative variance different in principle from interpretative variance engendered by the Florida Supreme Court in Bush v. Gore?

Irreducible Complexity in Coleman v. Franken

Minnesota is not Utopia.  The actual circumstances regarding the treatment of absentee ballots among Minnesota counties may differ from the highly stylized Utopia hypothetical, even as modified in various permutations. One of the basic truths about Coleman v. Franken is that it does not involve just one way in which localities are alleged to have treated absentee ballots unequally—like the Utopia hypothetical involving what qualifies as a “complete” voter address on the absentee ballot. Instead, in Coleman v. Franken the claim is that absentee ballots were treated unequally in a myriad of ways: signature matching, witness requirements, ballot delivery, and so forth.

It may well be that different arguments work to distinguish Coleman v. Franken from Bush v. Gore with respect to specific ways in which the localities are alleged to treat ballots unequally. The “differential resources” argument might work with respect to one specific category of alleged inequality (verifying a witness’s registration, for example), whereas it would be inapplicable to another (signature matching, for instance). Likewise, the “mistake” argument might work for some categories (perhaps ballot delivery) but not others (ID requirement).

But the trial court did not tie any particular argument to any specific category of alleged inequality. Instead, it rejected Coleman’s Equal Protection claim as a whole. This wholesale approach is somewhat surprising insofar as the same three judges were meticulous in proceeding specifically category-by-category to resolve questions of state law.    Whether surprising or not, the court’s approach in rejecting Coleman’s Equal Protection claim leaves an impression that the court’s work on this issue was somewhat unfinished. If the invocation of the Utopia hypothetical is persuasive in illustrating that it is not enough simply to say that Minnesota statutes on absentee ballots are clear, and/or that differences in available resources justifies local variation in the treatment of equivalent ballots, then the law professor is left hungry for more explanation on why Coleman’s claims should be rejected under Bush v. Gore. (Perhaps the law professor is never satisfied in searching for theoretical consistency, and that is why the legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin named his ideal judge Hercules.)

This analysis is not to suggest what the right answer would have been for each specific category of alleged inequality, if the trial court had undertaken that fact-intensive inquiry. I have not studied the trial record at that level of detail, especially with the view to ascertain whether “local mistake” or “local policy” applies in each instance.

The Paramount Value of Procedural Legitimacy

Moreover, even if I thought that the trial court “got it wrong” on the Equal Protection issue from a perspective of theoretical purity, it would not follow that I would want the Minnesota Supreme Court to reverse the trial court’s decision. As I have said repeatedly throughout this trial, because the Equal Protection issues in this case are particularly indeterminate in light of Bush v. Gore, it is more important the three judges are nonpartisan and unanimous on these issues—as they have been—than they reach any particular answer on these issues. Only if the Minnesota Supreme Court unanimously reverses the three judges in an opinion that is just as transparently nonpartisan would I believe that the public need for a fair and impartial resolution to this contentious election case has been as well served by that court as by the trial court’s decision.

I explore the Equal Protection issues on appeal, thus, not to give ground for reversing—or affirming—the trial court’s ruling. Rather, I do so out of a scholar’s sense of duty (or perhaps, more accurately, compulsion) to treat the issue with as much intellectual rigor and honesty as one can muster. If some of the discussion of the Equal Protection issues seems underdeveloped, then it is the scholar’s role to attempt to develop them. But the scholar can play this role and simultaneous think it is subsidiary to the paramount value of procedural legitimacy: ultimately, this case will be decided by a court of law, not by the academic musings, and the highest virtue of the judicial tribunal that finally settles this election is that its decision be maximally perceived by the public as the product of unbiased deliberation.

Whichever way the Minnesota Supreme Court rules on Equal Protection, if its ruling is perceived as politically motivated, then its resolution of the case will have fallen short according to this most important standard.

Out from the Shadows of Bush v. Gore

Now that we have a final decision from the trial court in Coleman v. Franken, it deserves recognition that this decision—because of the court’s composition and the deliberative process by which it conducted the process—satisfies the test of fairness identified way back in November.

If all the evidence and arguments for the Contestant and Contestee in Coleman v. Franken were the same and only the parties were reversed—so that Franken were the Contestant and Coleman the Contestee—there is virtually no doubt whatsoever that the same three-judge panel would have decided the case in exactly the same way. This strong confidence in the impartiality of the panel is the highest accolade one can bestow on a tribunal tasked with adjudicating a dispute in a major statewide election, particularly one involving significance to the two national political parties of this U.S. Senate seat.

It is, regrettably, not a judgment that one confidently could make about the U.S. Supreme Court in Bush v. Gore. The queasiness that many observers have about that case, even still more than eight years later, is that the Court majority would have rejected the Equal Protection claim there had Gore been the candidate making it. Thus, whatever else one says about the relationship of Coleman v. Franken and Bush v. Gore, the three-judge panel’s ruling is distinguishable for the simple reason of its evident impartiality.

That distinction arguably should be enough. If Minnesota law did not give the losing party in this case the right to an appeal, there would be no denial of justice. The ability of a candidate to receive a fair hearing before a structurally balanced tribunal—as this three-judge panel was, with its Democratic, Republican and Independent appointees—suffices to assure that the outcome deserves acceptance by the members of the public regardless of whom they voted for. Minnesota law, however, does allow for an appeal to the Minnesota Supreme Court. But when a trial court has been as evidentially impartial as this one, one might hope that the losing party does not try to get the higher court to reach a different outcome—a hope equally to be felt if Coleman had been the victor in this court. What does it say about any candidate who attempts to overturn an impartial ruling, based on the evidence and the law, which would have been the same even if the parties had been reversed in the case? Is the candidate simply trying to find a different tribunal that won’t be impartial?

To be sure, it is theoretically conceivable that a three-judge panel could be impartial and unanimous (as this one consistently has been) but mistaken, and that an equally impartial appellate court might unanimously reach the opposite conclusion. Theoretically conceivable, but quite unlikely. And what does Coleman think this three-judge court is mistaken about? The meaning and scope of Bush v. Gore. But Bush v. Gore is the precedent whose provenance is suspicious, given its apparent lack of impartiality.

Even if a conscientious judge distrusted the motives of the Court majority that decided Bush v. Gore, that judge would be obligated to follow it as precedent, so far as it goes. But how far does it go? Not far at all, according to the Court that issued it, at least on one plausible reading of its infamous self-limiting language: “Our consideration is limited to the present circumstances, for the problem of equal protection in election processes generally presents many complexities.” Even if Bush v. Gore governs a parcel of election law terrain, the reach of its authority is apparently not large and, at its outer edges, hazy.

If there never had been a Bush v. Gore, there seems little doubt that the Equal Protection claim in Coleman v. Franken would be a non-starter. That point seems just as true even supposing it had been Franken, rather than Coleman, making the Equal Protection claim. The three-judge panel cites precedent after precedent, from both federal and state courts, about the inability to claim an Equal Protection violation just because some state officials deviate from an ostensibly clear state statute. Bush v. Gore seems to be the only precedent that cuts the other way, an impression many observers had when it was decided.

But precedent it is, and one must ask: what if Franken, rather than Coleman, were relying on it? There is no doubt, as stated at the outset here, that this three-judge court would have rejected the same Equal Protection claim if raised by Franken rather than Coleman. But then would Franken be appealing to the Minnesota Supreme Court on the ground that the three-judge panel’s unanimous reading of Bush v. Gore was demonstrably mistaken? Would it be possible for Franken to show it so?

In a memorandum accompanying its final order, the three-judge court has written considerably—and conscientiously—about Bush v. Gore and its relevance to Coleman v. Franken. Much scholarly commentary undoubtedly will be devoted to the court’s analysis (Rick Hasen has already offered a thoughtful summary), and I plan to return to it myself after contemplating it more. But even in the first few hours after the release of this decision, it seems fair to say that the court’s rejection of Coleman’s Equal Protection claim—in addition to being impartial in the critical sense that the result would have been the same even had Franken been making the claim—cannot be characterized as an obvious misunderstanding of Bush v. Gore. Indeed, it might well be the correct understanding, the one that any other impartial tribunal would reach on the same facts.

In these circumstances, would the Minnesota Supreme Court wish to reach a different answer to the Equal Protection claim and risk appearing to lack the impartiality of this three-judge panel—and risk looking more like the U.S. Supreme Court in Bush v. Gore itself? In this respect, Bush v. Gore is a precedent that no fair-minded court would want to emulate. This negative example of how not to act judicially, rather than the specific contours of its Equal Protection ruling, may be that case’s most important legacy—and Coleman v. Franken, insofar as it distinguishes itself from Bush v. Gore in this respect, may be a major step in restoring the judiciary’s image of being able to decide a nationally prominent statewide election contest impartially.

Situation Normal: Election Too Close to Call

The news that yesterday’s special congressional election in New York will depend on the counting of absentee and provisional ballots should not be viewed as another episode of abnormally bad “electoral weather,” following on the heels of the still-undecided U.S. Senate election in Minnesota.

To be sure, most elections are insufficiently competitive such that initial Election Night returns are enough to predict the eventual official winner—and thus provoke a gracious concession from the inevitable loser. But our electoral system won’t be healthy unless and until the public perceives it capable of handling in a straightforward way a truly competitive election that actually requires counting every vote, including all the absentee and provisional ballots.

An election in which the concession speech is given upon the declaration of the officially certified result—after administrative review of all the absentee and provisional ballots, and without protracted judicial litigation over the outcome—should be seen as a successful conclusion of the electoral process. Consider it another kind of “normal,” a resolution much less frequent than the Election Night concession speech but an equal (if not greater) vindication of democracy. Waiting for official certification before we know the outcome, in other words, need not be seen as evidence of a dysfunctional democracy.

Another way to put this point is to remember what should be obvious but is often overlooked: elections that are too close to call on Election Night do not all play out the same way in their “endgame” scenarios. Some spin out of control into months or years of protracted judicial litigation. Others resolve themselves quickly in a matter of days or weeks.  The variables that affect the quality of the endgame resolution of these “initially too close to call elections” include the officially certified margin of victory (which might be quite a bit wider than the initial Election Night returns), the degree of sloppiness in the administration of the vote casting-and-counting process (which gives grounds for judicial litigation), and the quality of a state’s institutions for handling these electoral endgame scenarios.

Even election results that end up in court fights, before a concession speech occurs, can yield different kinds of outcomes varying in the quality of their resolution from a perspective of public acceptance and democratic legitimacy. Better to avoid a court fight if possible; but if not, better that it be resolved relatively quickly and with a sense of impartial fairness. That’s why it is still too early to pass judgment on Minnesota’s U.S. Senate election: we do know that the combined recount-plus-contest has taken far longer than desirable, but we still don’t know what kind of closure ultimately will be reached.

To better understand these electoral endgame scenarios, and how their handling might be improved, my Moritz colleague Steve Huefner and I are in the process of researching and writing a book on this topic. Our work so far has caused us to be sensitive to distinctions between types of elections and the context in which close outcomes occur. The fact that this special congressional election in New York involves a House, rather than Senate, seat is an important factor even if this distinction does not appear in the doctrinal jurisprudence of New York law involving disputed elections. So too is the fact that the fight over Minnesota’s Senate seat, as national Democrats try to get one vote closer to a 60-seat filibuster-proof supramajority while national Republicans try to prevent that outcome, has much higher stakes than whether the House Democrats get one more seat to pad their majority in that filibuster-free chamber.

But our work has also caused us to be cautious about overstating the significance of these kinds of political contextual distinctions. There are, for example, important differences between gubernatorial and U.S. Senate elections. Still, however, there are enough similarities between these two kinds of statewide races that comparison between Minnesota’s 1962 gubernatorial election and its current dispute over the U.S. Senate seat has been highly illuminating—just as long as that comparison is not taken too far.

Our research for the book has also taken a historical turn, even before the comparison of the two Minnesota statewide examples showed the benefit of historical inquiry. Thus, before jumping to any conclusions about the significance of this new “too close to call” election in New York, it is worth putting it in the context of the fact that New York has seen over the centuries a lot of elections too close to call on Election Night, including the presidential elections of 1880, 1884, and 1888—when the outcome of the presidency depended on the resolution of New York’s Electoral College votes, but that outcome could not be known for days or in 1884 for a couple of weeks. Yet New York was able to bring these razor-thin presidential elections to relatively quick resolution and without resort to judicial litigation, in stark contrast to what had occurred in 1876 (or eventually again in 2000). Understanding why 1884 was successful whereas 1876 was not, for example, will be a major objective of our book.

To invoke another historical reference, New York had what appears to be the first major disputed election of our new nation: the dispute over its 1792 gubernatorial election between incumbent George Clinton and challenger John Jay. I invoke that historical example in the context of today’s “too close to call” election from New York for this specific reason: as I describe in a lecture on this “Original Bush v. Gore,” our Founding Fathers were uncertain about how to handle disputed elections. Their uncertainty is a legacy that persists to today.

As part of the commentary over the disputed U.S Senate seat from Minnesota, there has been a dialogue between those who believe that some elections are simply too close for our vote-counting procedures to handle and thus there should be a run-off, or flip of the coin, when the apparent margin of victory is within a certain range. (Presumably, one would still need to wait for the counting of absentee and provisional ballots to see if an election fell within this “statistical tie” situation.) Others argue with equal vigor that an election system premised on one-person-one-vote must proceed, however difficult it may be, to declare a winner as long as one candidate is determined to have one more valid vote than the other; a coin toss or run-off must be reserved for an actual, not statistical, tie.

The fact that we are having this dialogue in its current form, at the level of first principles about the purpose and design of our voting process, indicates to me how little we have progressed as a nation in developing a shared understanding on how to think about, and thus handle, elections with razor-thin results. This lack of progress is puzzling and another agenda item for our book to address. We’ve advanced our thinking in so many other fields of human endeavor: hard sciences, social sciences, educational practices, and so forth. Why not this one? It’s not as if close elections are truly infrequent phenomena. They may be relatively rare, especially in presidential elections, but our society has had enough “too close to call” elections for local races that the legal system recognizes it is a matter that requires attention. The problem is culturally we still haven’t really figured out what sort of attention we want our legal system to give it.

Maybe this new “too close to call” election from New York will disappear quickly. Maybe, for example, the count of absentee and provisional ballots will make the winner obvious. A gracious concession speech will occur, and this blip on the radar screen won’t even deserve a footnote in our book. That would be a victory for New York, indicating a successful result according to the alternative “normal” process described above.   But our societal or cultural uncertainty over how to think about “too close to call” elections, as evidenced by the “statistical tie” debate, will continue whatever happens with this particular episode.

Unsurprising Ruling Does Not End Minnesota Senate Case

“We told you so” is essentially what the three-judge court said in today’s ruling.  But the ruling does not address Coleman’s Equal Protection claim.  When the court finally resolves that issue, the court’s decision will be the definitive one–at least pending an appeal.

“We told you so” is essentially what the three-judge court said in today’s ruling. In its now-famous (at least among followers of this case) February 13 order, the court made clear that it would adopt a strict reading of the state’s statutes concerning the casting and counting of absentee ballots. In other statements along the way, the court similarly made plain that this strict reading would require both candidates to meet specific evidentiary burdens in order for additional absentee ballots to be counted as a result of the trial.

Thus, it comes as no surprise that the court has now ruled in effect that Coleman largely failed to meet this evidentiary obligation. What is surprising is that Coleman never really attempted to satisfy the evidentiary standard that the court had clearly identified. Franken, by contrast, when it was his turn to present evidence for the counting of additional ballots he wanted added to post-recount/pre-contest totals, for the most part appeared to follow the evidentiary rules that the court set forth. The fact that he was able to do so makes it all the more puzzling why Coleman never made the effort.

Instead, it seems that after the February 13 order Coleman shifted his trial strategy to focus exclusively on his Equal Protection argument: his claim that the supremacy of federal constitutional law necessitates abandoning strict compliance with Minnesota’s statutory rules even if state law, in the absence of any federal constitutional considerations, would call for the kind of strict compliance articulated in the February 13 order.

That Equal Protection argument remains unaddressed by today’s ruling. It is the subject of major pending motions that have yet to be resolved. The three judges have sent strong signals that they are not favorably disposed to Coleman’s Equal Protection claim. Yet it still casts a shadow over the case, as the major unresolved issue. It has the potential of dwarfing today’s ruling in significance since it implicates a far greater number of ballots. Another way to put this point: if Coleman were somehow able to prevail on his Equal Protection claim, it wouldn’t matter that he failed to meet the evidentiary burdens that governed today’s ruling (and reiterated the February 13 order). Perhaps that’s the reason why he never really tried to satisfy the court’s evidentiary standard: he knew his case ultimately turned entirely on the Equal Protection claim; the rest was essentially inconsequential.

Thus, it remains necessary still to wait for what more the three judges will say about the Equal Protection claim.   Since they last addressed it formally in pre-trial “summary judgment” motions, they have heard evidence of inconsistent policies and/or practices among counties on how to handle various recurring issues concerning absentee ballots. The potential implications of this evidence are tricky given the murkiness of Equal Protection principles articulated in Bush v. Gore—a point I’ve discussed previously and won’t repeat here. Bottom-line: Coleman’s Equal Protection claim is hardly a slam-dunk winner. But various possible refined and narrower versions of this argument, depending on the strength of the relevant evidence, are not obvious slam-dunk losers, either, under Bush v. Gore. For this reason, it remains important how the three-judge court explains its final ruling on the Equal Protection claim, even if all observers expect the court to rule against Coleman.

Given all the talk (including by Coleman’s own attorneys) of an eventual appeal to the Minnesota Supreme Court on the Equal Protection issue, the posture of that appeal will be affected by how persuasive the three-judge trial court is in its analysis of this issue in light of the relevant evidence. The likelihood of a split decision in the Minnesota Supreme Court on the Equal Protection issue—for example, 3-2 one way or the other—diminishes in relation to the increased cogency of the three-judge court in its own unanimous treatment of the issue. I’m assuming the continued unanimity of these three judges on the Equal Protection issue, but it seems a safe assumption given their unbroken unanimity so far.

The Original Bush v. Gore: An Historical Perspective on Disputed Elections

I am here posting a draft of a lecture I delivered last fall on the 1792 disputed gubernatorial election in New York.  This lecture will serve as the basis for the first of a series of chapters in a book (co-authored with my Moritz colleague Steve Huefner) that discusses significant disputed elections throughout U.S. history.  I am posting the draft now because I frequently refer in other work to this inaugural disputed election in our republic’s history–and the lessons we can learn from this historical inquiry.  To the extent that the availability of this draft can assist the development of scholarship in the field, prior to the publication of the book, this posting of it will be beneficial.

Reluctance to Void Elections – Some Memorable Cases

By Nathan Cemenska

Web Editor, Election Law @ Moritz
Moritz College of Law

The closeness and counting irregularities in the ongoing Minnesota Senate contest have prompted discussion of just voiding the result and calling a new election.  Regardless of whether granting such a remedy is good policy, it is unlikely to happen under Minnesota law, just as it would be unlikely to happen in any state.  In fact, despite the fact that I’ve read hundreds of election contest lawsuits, I’ve read only a handful that granted any kind of meaningful remedy, and even fewer that voided an entire election.  Here are good examples of cases that appeared to have some merit but ultimately failed.

Election for Ohio Attorney General (1990).  In this case, the Supreme Court of Ohio denied an election contest by Paul Pfeiffer claiming that he was the true winner of the 1990 election for AG.  Pfeiffer lost the initial count by 1,234 votes but proved to the Ohio Supreme Court that the candidates’ names on 94,869 ballots had not been rotated properly.  In re Election of Nov. 6, 1990 for Office of Atty. Gen. of Ohio, 569 N.E.2d 447 (Ohio, 1991).  The court acknowledged “that improper ballot rotation could have an effect,” but said that “the extent of this effect depends on the record developed in each case.”  Id. at 454.  After describing expert testimony from both sides regarding the effect of the improper ballot rotation, the court concluded that it affected vote totals somewhere between zero and ten percent, but “that the correct percentage would be closer to zero than ten percent.”  Id. at 455.   Using this percentage, the court determined that the contestant failed to prove by clear and convincing evidence that the improper ballot rotation made the true result of the election uncertain.  Id. at 457.  Paul Pfeiffer now sits on the Supreme Court of Ohio.

Election for Illinois Governor (1982).  The initial count showed incumbent Jim Thompson ahead of Adlai Stevenson by 5,074 votes out of about 3.6 million cast statewide. In re Contest for Governor, 444 N.E.2d 170, 172 (Ill., 1983). Stevenson obtained a partial “discovery recount” in precincts in 70 counties to generate evidence for an election contest.  Id. at 179.  Based on that discovery recount, Stevenson filed an election contest alleging that some improper duplicate ballots were counted, that ballots were improperly counted despite the fact that they were not initialed or initialed only partially by election judges, that some were counted despite having identifying marks upon them, and that some were counted despite being cast by ineligible voters.  Id. at 181.  Stevenson alleged that if these errors were corrected, it would have put him ahead by 4,664 votes.  Id. at 180. Stevenson hoped to use the discovery provisions of the election contest laws to find still more votes in his favor.

However, the Illinois Supreme Court dismissed the lawsuit, and did so in a curious way.  Instead of following the normal standard that decides a motion to dismiss, the court did not assume, for purposes of the motion, that the facts stated in the complaint were true.  Instead, the court went “behind the pleadings” to look at the conduct of the original partial recount and then dismissed the case because it said that Adlai Stevenson had no reasonable cause to complain about the conduct of the counting and recounting activities. A grand jury later determined that Adlai Stevenson had unwittingly benefited from some 100,000 illegal ballots that had been cast in Chicago in the 1982 gubernatorial election.  U.S. to Probe Primary Vote Fraud, Chicago Tribune, March 11, 1987.  The Illinois legislature later changed election contest procedures based on the court’s ruling.

Election for Washington governor (2004).  Two initial recounts showed that Rossi (R) was ahead but the third and final recount showed Gregoire (D) up by 129 votes out of 2.9 million cast.  The case ended up in the Chelan County Superior Court where, despite having concluded that 1,678 illegal ballots were counted in the election, the court would not grant a remedy for Rossi’s allegation that “it was impossible to determine which gubernatorial candidate received the greatest number of legitimate votes” (see here).  The court refused to hear evidence concerning the political predilections of the voters who had cast illegal ballots.

Will the Franken/Coleman litigation join this dustbin of “close but no cigar”cases?  Well, in general a plaintiff who wants to win an election contest has to have very credible evidence of who should have won.  The defendant, on the other hand, in most states (including Minnesota) can usually prevail if the evidence is murky and the true result is unclear.  Furthermore, in very very close statewide elections like Franken/Coleman, the result is always going to be “murky” in some way due to the close margin and the inability to eliminate small human errors.  That puts the defendant in a pretty good position.

By Sarah Cherry

Analyst, Election Law @ Moritz
Moritz College of Law

The Minnesota Supreme Court’s 1975 decision in Bell v. Gannaway, 303 Minn. 346, (Minn. 1975) has received quite a lot of attention lately. A couple of things about Bell need more discussion. First, how significant to the court’s holding was its finding that candidates had the opportunity on election day to challenge invalid absentee ballots? Has that law and practice changed? Second, would the court have reached the same conclusion if it had been dealing with a contest of a statewide race like Coleman v. Franken? Does that matter now? Finally, what factual findings and reasoning would lead today’s contest court to reach a different conclusion than the court in Bell

What has to happen to unring this Bell

The Minnesota Supreme Court’s 1975 decision in Bell v. Gannaway, 303 Minn. 346, (Minn. 1975) has received quite a lot of attention lately. MinnPost.com’s Eric Black has written two analyses of the case. They are here and here. I wrote a piece about it as well here. A couple of things about Bell need more discussion. First, how significant to the court’s holding was its finding that candidates had the opportunity on election day to challenge invalid absentee ballots? Has that law and practice changed? Second, would the court have reached the same conclusion if it had been dealing with a contest of a statewide race like Coleman v. Franken? Does that matter now? Finally, what factual findings and reasoning would lead today’s contest court to reach a different conclusion than the court in Bell?

Challenges – election day and after

The Bell court revealed its dismay at having to hold that a clearly invalid ballot had to remain in the count because of statutory language regarding the timing of challenges to ballots. The statute that formed the basis of Bell read in 1975:

The voter and the ballots of any absent voter at any time before the ballots have been deposited in the ballot boxes are subject to a challenge by the judges or by any person who was not present at the time the voter procured the ballots, but not otherwise.

Bell at 805, quoting former M.S.A. 204.11(4). The court seized upon the phrase “but not otherwise” and construed it “to mean that an absentee ballot may not be challenged at any time after the ballot has been deposited in the ballot box.” Id. The new version of the statute, M.S.A. 204C.13, similarly reads:

At any time before the ballots of any voter are deposited into the ballot boxes, the election judges or any individual who was not present at the time the voter procured the ballots, but not otherwise, may challenge the eligibility of that voter and the deposit of any received absentee ballots in the ballot boxes.

The language, while arranged differently, is still ambiguous. The Bell court acknowledged that the statute’s phrase “but not otherwise” could be read to modify who can bring challenges rather than when challenges can be made. But the court went with the latter reading saying the legislature would have to clear this up if it found the court had assigned the wrong meaning to the words of the statute. (My previous piece on Bell also discusses this statutory language.) The statute was changed to its current wording in 1978 and any legislative history that might explain the reason for the change or any new intended meaning is not easily available. A law librarian at the University of Minnesota told me that audio tapes of the committee hearings are the only records available and are likely stored at the Minnesota Historical Society. My assumption is that helpful comments that would explain the change probably do not exist, but I will gladly admit error if someone in Minnesota would like to sift through those tapes looking for clues.

Bell’s reasoning as to the timing of challenges appeared to also depend on the assumption that challengers were supposed to and had the opportunity to challenge ballots at the polling place before they were deposited in the ballot box and irretrievably commingled with valid ballots. The Bell court cited MSA 204.17 in support of the proposition that candidates have a statutory right to inspect and challenge improperly completed absentee ballot envelopes on election night before they are deposited into the ballot box under the statute’s language permitting challengers to challenge voters’ eligibility. Today’s MSA 204C.12 says in almost identical language to MSA 204.17 “An election judge shall, and an authorized challenger or other voter may, challenge an individual whom the person knows or reasonably believes is not an eligible voter.”

So, the law appears to be the same but what about the practice? Ramsey County Elections Director Joe Mansky told MinnPost.com that it is not possible for candidate representatives to challenge the deposit of absentee ballots into the ballot box (candidates do not appoint their own challengers in partisan elections) but that challengers appointed by the political parties may do so. However, he said that such party challengers never do this. Perhaps this is because the absentee ballots have already been examined and accepted at the county level before being transported to the precincts for counting. While the law then and now says nothing explicit about challengers being permitted to inspect and challenge the proper completion of absentee ballot envelopes, the Bell court interpreted the law permitting challenge to voter qualification to allow such inspection and challenge of absentee ballots. Evidence of the practice that has developed (or disappeared) since 1975 could shed light on whether the basic assumptions underlying Bell’s holding are still valid.

What would the Bell court have done with a case like Coleman v. Franken?

The Bell court could very well have come to a different conclusion had it been dealing with a statewide race where not one but thousands of ballots were in dispute. Bell involved an election for township supervisor in which just over 200 votes were cast (fewer than the margin now separating Franken and Coleman) and the decision came down to a single vote that was invalid due to both an official error and a voter error. The official witnessed the ballot before giving it to the voter’s husband to take to her and the voter did not sign the ballot envelope. Her vote was opened and counted by the election judges on election night. Would the Bell court have let that woman’s ballot remain in the count if all of the mistakes had been made by her with no contribution by the election official who issued the ballot? The dissent calls her failure to sign the envelope a flagrant violation of the law but is it really flagrant to forget to sign your ballot envelope? Perhaps it would be a flagrant violation to vote without registering or to have “Lizard People” witness your ballot. But not signing the envelope, while a serious defect, is not necessarily a flagrant and willful violation on the part of a voter that was more likely just forgetful.

As to challengers, did the Bell court really hold that candidates in any election must have a challenger in every polling place or lose his or her opportunity to challenge invalid votes? The majority attempted to address the dissent’s criticism of this burdensome requirement by saying it’s not completely out of bounds to expect such staffing of polls with challengers and noting besides that the election in Bell involved a single precinct. It was as if to say it needn’t cross that bridge now because this was a small election where it is entirely reasonable to expect a challenger to have been on duty and to have challenged this particular ballot for lack of a voter signature.

One difference between the 1975 Bell circumstances and today’s contest is that township supervisor was apparently a nonpartisan office. The Bell court discussed MSA 204.16 subd. 2 which, like its successor, today’s MSA 204C. 07, permits candidates for nonpartisan office to appoint challengers to be present at the polls on election day. It was this kind of challenger that the Bell court argued could have challenged the invalid absentee ballot on election night. Both MSA 204.16 and today’s MSA 204C.07 also provide that political parties appoint the challengers for partisan elections and that only one per party at a time may be present in the polling place. In Coleman v. Franken, a partisan race is being contested in which candidates were not permitted to appoint their own representatives to act as challengers. Political parties, however, were authorized to appoint challengers that theoretically could have acted on Coleman’s behalf. This may be a meaningless difference since challengers, no matter how appointed, have the same duties and their actions are controlled by the same statutes. But it is a difference nonetheless.

Conclusion

As we lawyers and commentators always say, it is impossible to know what this court will do. It has referred to Bell’s requirement of strict compliance with absentee ballot laws multiple times but it has not yet commented on whether or not Bell requires challenges to the inclusion of absentee ballots to be made before they are deposited into the ballot box. Following past precedent is a core feature of the American justice system, but that, of course, does not mean that laws and the interpretations of laws do not change over time. While outright overruling of past decisions is rare, it is not so rare for a court to distinguish one set of facts from another in the distant past so that a new legal conclusion must be reached. In this case, it would not be impossible for the contest court to reason that Bell does not require in every case that invalid ballots remain in the count just because they were not challenged before they were commingled. If the practice has changed with respect to what challengers are permitted to do at the polls, for example, it would be possible for the contest court to arrive at a different conclusion about what should be done with invalid ballots. This contest court may well agree with the dissenters in Bell that limiting the time frame for permissible challenges to election night in every case could result in violations far more serious than forgetting to sign a ballot envelope controlling the outcome of an election. The court could, therefore, decide that the Bell rule is not to be universally applied to elections large and small, complex and simple.

Un-counting votes in Minnesota’s U.S. Senate race

By Sarah Cherry

Analyst, Election Law @ Moritz
Moritz College of Law

Question: Assuming that invalid absentee votes have been cast and counted in Minnesota’s U.S. Senate race without any way to retrieve them, what remedy does Minnesota law provide when the number of such invalid absentee ballots exceeds the margin of victory?

This comment addresses a scenario which is not yet ripe for judicial consideration in that Coleman has not (yet) shown that there were more invalid votes counted than the number that now separates the two candidates—and it is possible that the court will consider him procedurally barred from raising this issue at this stage of the trial. For our purposes, we will define valid and invalid votes in accordance with the court’s Feb. 13 order. (Reference is made to “legal” and “illegal” votes in the following analysis because that is how the case law refers to them.) We will assume that Coleman can and will prove that enough invalid ballots were included in the count to possibly alter the outcome of the election. Coleman has produced a list of ballots where the witness’ registrations were not confirmed by county officials before officials accepted absentee ballots, but these are not automatically invalid ballots as many of the unconfirmed witnesses likely were registered. However, Coleman’s preliminary analysis of 5 counties and municipalities shows just under 100 ballots that do not comply with the contest court’s Feb. 13 order. He would likely find more than 225 invalid ballots if such a pattern held up statewide. Coleman has made a motion to have the Feb. 13 order applied to all absentee ballots cast and counted on and since election day.

Where invalid absentee votes have been commingled and counted with legal votes, there are several possible remedies: 1) leave the invalid votes in the count and count the remaining votes in strict accordance with the law – two wrongs do not make a right; 2) remove the invalid votes from the total of the candidate for whom they were cast, (assuming this can be determined); 3) remove the invalid votes from the total votes counted by proportionally deducting them from each candidates’ totals by precinct, city, or county (assuming that it cannot be determined for whom the invalid votes were cast); 4) invalidate the election because it cannot be determined for whom the invalid votes were cast. Minnesota law is unclear on exactly which course must be taken. The court’s orders indicate that it is leaning toward option 1, to count votes prospectively in strict accordance with the law regardless of how they were counted prior to the contest. The court does not appear to believe that there were systematic problems with Minnesota’s election system such that an equal protection violation exists, but it has not finally ruled on this issue.

1. Leave the invalid votes in the count; count the remaining ballots in strict accordance with the law.

The court seems to be leaning this way but may have some problems sticking to this path if Coleman indeed comes up with a large number of invalid votes. Coleman’s memo in support of his motion to apply the Feb. 13 order to all absentees cites a 1994 Supreme Court case, Rivers v. Roadway Express, Inc. 511 U.S. 298 (1994), for the proposition that a court’s interpretation of statute is an authoritative statement as to what the statute meant before as well as what it means now. The actual quote is, “A judicial construction of a statute is an authoritative statement of what the statute meant before as well as after the decision of the case giving rise to that construction.” Rivers at 313. Footnote 12 explains, “But when this Court construes a statute, it is explaining its understanding of what the statute has meant continuously since the date when it became law.” Id. The Rivers argument may be a weak one in that U.S. Supreme Court opinions may not be authoritative on how Minnesota courts interpret Minnesota law. Coleman is trying to show the 3-judge court that the Rivers approach should be persuasive by analogy.

During the Feb. 27 hearing on Coleman’s motion to have all absentee ballot envelopes reviewed in search of invalidly cast ballots, Judge Marben asked Coleman’s attorney James Langdon why the court should not follow the Minnesota Supreme Court’s 1975 decision in Bell v. Gannaway, 227 N.W.2d 797 (Minn., 1975) and hold that absentee ballots may not be challenged after they are deposited in the ballot box. In response, Langdon said that Bell dealt with a statute for challenging ballots on election day and that, today, challengers are not armed with the knowledge they need to object to the counting of absentee ballots.

In Bell, Bell contested the election of Gannaway to the office of township supervisor which Gannaway had won by one vote. The crucial vote in that case was cast absentee by a woman who neglected to sign the ballot certificate and who had not properly observed the witness requirements because a town official had filled in the witness portion of her ballot envelope before she even received it. The statute that formed the basis of Bell read in 1975:

The voter and the ballots of any absent voter at any time before the ballots have been deposited in the ballot boxes are subject to a challenge by the judges or by any person who was not present at the time the voter procured the ballots, but not otherwise.

Bell at 805, quoting former M.S.A. 204.11(4). The court seized upon the phrase “but not otherwise” and construed it “to mean that an absentee ballot may not be challenged at any time after the ballot has been deposited in the ballot box.” Id. The new version of the statute, M.S.A. 204C.13, similarly reads:

At any time before the ballots of any voter are deposited into the ballot boxes, the election judges or any individual who was not present at the time the voter procured the ballots, but not otherwise, may challenge the eligibility of that voter and the deposit of any received absentee ballots in the ballot boxes.

The language, while arranged differently, is still ambiguous. Minnesota law still allows one challenger per candidate to be present at the polls during voting and vote-counting so it is not clear what changes Langdon was referring to when he implied that the statutes then and now were significantly different.

The court has cited Bell several times in its orders in support of the requirement of strict compliance with absentee statutes and to point out that fraud prevention is a key concern in the policy underlying the development of Minnesota absentee ballot law. It would appear contradictory for the court to hold that Bell requires them to allow the counting of ballots that they know to be invalid according to their Feb. 13 order simply because it interprets Minnesota law to require challenges to absentee ballots to be made on election day. The court in 1975 had an easier decision to make as they were dealing with only one deficient absentee ballot.

2. Determine for whom the invalid votes were cast and remove them from the candidates’ totals accordingly.

This remedy assumes that it can be determined for whom any invalid votes were cast. It would be a massive and lengthy undertaking for Coleman to gather and present persuasive evidence that enough invalid votes were cast for Franken to render Franken’s lead invalid. In past Minnesota contests that have resulted in published judicial opinions, the number of votes in dispute has been very small – from one or two votes to a couple of dozen. (This analysis does not yet include a thorough study of the 1962 gubernatorial election contest and recount which may have seen discussion of un-counting invalid votes that would inform today’s debate.) Even if Coleman could get enough voters on the stand to testify as to who they voted for, it is unclear in Minnesota law whether this would be permitted because it would harm the confidence of the public in the secrecy of their ballot if they thought they might someday have to tell the world how they voted in a court room. Coleman’s position appears to be that he does not know yet for whom any invalid ballots were cast or if enough were cast to overturn the election’s outcome but also that they cannot know this without investigating via this contest.

A Minnesota appeals court held that when illegal ballots are inseparably commingled with legal ballots, the contestant can sustain an election contest by showing that the contestee did not get a majority of legal votes. Kearin v. Roach, 381 N.W.2d 531 (Minn.App., 1986). The only way to do this is by showing that a sufficient number of illegal votes were cast for the contestee to change the result of the election. According to the Kearin court, the right to ballot secrecy deprives the contestant of offering direct testimony of how illegal votes were cast, but “circumstantial evidence is sufficient to sustain a contestant’s burden of proof if it has the requisite degree of persuasion.” Id. at 533. However, the 1917 Minnesota Supreme Court case that Kearin cites for that proposition actually did not disallow direct evidence of how a voter voted. It merely did not require it. Berg v. Veit, 162 N.W. 522 (1917). Berg involved no attempt to prove for whom the invalid ballots were cast. However, in a 1924 case, Mathison v. Meyer, 159 Minn. 438 (Minn. 1924), the contestant showed that voters of invalid ballots had worked on the contestee’s campaign, and that was enough circumstantial evidence to find that the ballots had been cast for contestee. It is unclear what will happen if Coleman does not have any evidence of this kind; will he be entitled to rely on proportionate deduction, may he subpoena voters notwithstanding their right to secrecy, or will he necessarily lose?

3. Remove the invalid votes from the total votes counted by removing them from each candidates’ totals pro rata by precinct

There is no Minnesota case law requiring that this remedy be employed. This remedy may be available if it cannot be determined for whom the invalid votes were counted, but it is not clear what kind of burden the contestant would have to meet to obtain such a remedy. No Minnesota case exists where this remedy has been implemented. In a 1917 Minnesota Supreme Court case, the court appeared to leave the door open to this remedy being used but said that the contestant would have to satisfy the court that he could not prove for whom any illegal ballots were cast. Berg v. Veit, 136 Minn. 443, (1917). The court said, “Purging an election of illegal votes by deducting a pro rata part of them from the votes for each candidate is justifiable only when it is impossible to show for whom they were actually cast.” In Berg, the court found that evidence existed that could have been introduced to show for whom any illegal ballots were cast but that contestant did not attempt to introduce it nor to persuade the court that the truth of how the ballots were cast could not be ascertained.

In a 1941 decision, the court, while not shutting the door for good on the pro rata method, did not use it or necessarily clear the way for its use. Coleman cites in support of his motion Hanson v. Emanuel, 210 Minn. 271, 297 N.W. 749 (Minn. 1941) for the proposition that illegal votes cannot be counted at all, let alone apportioned between candidates. The court said, “We referred in [Berg], to certain cases holding that illegal votes may be apportioned where it cannot be ascertained for whom they were cast…” (The court is referring to cases in other states cited by Berg.) In Hanson, the court was discussing a vote known to have been illegally cast for a certain candidate that had been apportioned between the candidates, each getting half of the vote, rather than excluded altogether.

Coleman did not mention the pro rata deduction remedy in his motion and only mentioned it for the first time in the Feb. 27 hearing. In the memorandum supporting his motion, Coleman’s team did not engage in the analysis above which leaves one to wonder whether they think the court will entertain such a remedy or if they instead are still seriously seeking to have the court reconsider its Feb. 13 order which strictly limited the definition of a legally cast ballot. Coleman’s team did cite another case, Johnson v. Trnka, 154 N.W. 2d 185, 187 (1967), for the proposition that “The outcome of an election should rest upon ballots received according to law and should not be determined by illegal votes.” This case is distinguishable from Coleman v. Franken in that Minnesota statute provides a remedy of random withdrawal when there are excess ballots (more ballots than voters signed in), as there were in Johnson, but provides no such explicit remedy when illegally cast ballots are commingled and included in the count. M.S.A. 204C.20; 206.86.

Some states have employed pro rata deduction. For example, in 1991, an Illinois court approved the pro rata deduction method of removing illegal ballots in an alderman election. People ex rel. Ciaccio v. Martin220 Ill.App.3d 89, 580 N.E.2d, 930 Ill.App. 3 (Dist.,1991). But, it is not a common remedy and Minnesota law does not provide for it in statute.

4. Invalidate the election

It does not appear that this court will invalidate the election. This remedy may not be available as it is not explicitly spelled out in statute and the court has a duty to determine which candidate received the most votes. Even if this cannot be done to the satisfaction of statisticians, it is not a legally impossible task. The Minnesota Supreme Court in 1955 did invalidate the votes from an entire precinct in an election where many rules had been broken in the precinct and, while no fraud was shown, the circumstances were ripe for fraud to have taken place. The court held that the absence of fraud will not always mean an election was valid where so great an opportunity for fraud was created by ignoring the election laws. In re Contest of Election of Vetsch, 245 Minn. 229 (1955). In no case since Vetsch has a Minnesota court found such a complete disregard for election laws that the true will of the people was not reflected in an election’s outcome, requiring the invalidation of a jurisdiction’s entire vote. That case had to do with fraud and the circumstances that foster fraud, and neither of these conditions are alleged by Franken or Coleman to have existed in the November 2008 election.

Conclusion

Coleman has provisionally rested his case as of March 2, 2009. As Franken prepares to present his case, the court must decide whether to grant or deny Coleman’s motion to apply the Feb. 13 order to all absentee ballots. It is impossible to predict what the contest court will do, but its orders so far have shown a desire to give Minnesotans a final answer as to which candidate received the most votes for U.S. Senate. Reopening deliberations on all 280,000 absentee ballots would significantly delay the result. On the other hand, the court has not fully disposed of the equal protection claim that Coleman has tried to keep alive throughout the contest. The court must now either leave allegedly invalid ballots in the count, attempt to remove them or decide that it cannot be determined who received the most votes in this election. Thankfully, such a decision is near at hand and, hopefully, the court will be unanimous in its conclusion.

Coin-flipping: Is it a good idea?

By Nathan Cemenska

Web Editor, Election Law @ Moritz
Moritz College of Law

In 2006, Indiana University law professor Mike Pitts published an entertaining law review article in which he argued that, when an election is so close that it amounts to a “statistical tie,” the judiciary should acknowledge this by not even attempting to determine the “true” result. Heads or Tails? A Modest Proposal for Deciding Close Elections, 39 CTLR 739 (Dec., 2006). Instead, Pitts argued, they should just flip a coin to determine the winner and be done with it. Pitts argument was an obvious reaction to the morass of 2000, but similar sentiments have been echoed in the New York Times and regional newspapers since the Minnesota Senate recount began. But is coin-flipping really a good idea, or just a provocative one?

First let me say that I became infatuated with the coin-flipping idea when I first heard about it. Here, I said to myself, here is a way to shut up all the lawyers and judges and have the thing decided by a truly neutral and objective process (when it comes to resolving election difficulties, lawyers and judges are in my view generally the problem, not the solution). The idea also appealed to a certain independent streak in me that does not like being asked to accept a result that has no statistical validity. Finally, I thought a coin-flip would preserve some degree of respect for the democratic process in the mind of the average person, who would be spared by the coin from having to see more photos like the infamous magnifying glass photo of 2000 (a photograph that by itself probably did more to discredit the voting process than the actions of any candidate or court). I did recognize that the coin-flipping would cause a great deal of angst in those who want to be able to idealize the democratic process in their minds, but that was a price I was willing to pay (or have them pay) to keep the average people (including myself) from becoming even more cynical.

However, the honeymoon is over and, thanks to a Moritz colleague, I can no longer subscribe to this idea. The main problem is not the basic idea of coin-flipping but, as my colleague pointed out, the implementation. Specifically, it would be difficult if not impossible to implement the idea in a way that will accomplish the goal of eliminating troublesome litigation. If you pass a law that says election contests within a certain margin will be determined by a coin-flip, then people will file lawsuits to influence the result of any earlier recount proceedings and push the result across that margin (recounts occur before election contests in almost every state). You have not eliminated the troublesome litigation, you’ve only pushed it back so that it occurs at an earlier point in the process.

Mike Pitts is no dummy and thought of this problem. The solution he proposes is this: Pretend that the “triggering margin” is 0.5% of the total vote, so that any race won by fewer than that margin would be decided by a coin flip. Now, in a statewide race candidate A loses to candidate B by 0.6% of the vote. Ordinarily this would mean candidate A could still get a coin flip by closing the margin in a recount by just a little over 0.1% of the vote. However, under Pitts’ regime, this 0.1% would not be enough. Instead, in order to get a coin flip the recount would have to show not only that candidate A came within the coin-flip margin, but that candidate A actually got more votes than candidate B. In other words, candidate A would have to move the count by 0.6% of the vote, a formidable task in a statewide election where the sample size is large enough to absorb most types of errors without changing the result. This would squelch most attempts at disputing the result in an election contest, and also attempts to use litigation to influence any recounts.

Trouble is, candidates can get around this litigation-squelching effect by pushing the litigation still earlier into the process, so that it occurs on the eve of the election when polls show the result will be close, or even during the counting process itself. Because a final count has not yet been determined, Pitts’ rule would not apply and there would be nothing to discourage candidates from filing a series of mandamus actions to influence whether the eventual count falls within the coin-flipping margin. And this kind of last-minute, catch-all litigation is a bad thing, worse than the kind that occurs after the election, because at best it delays the count and at worst makes a muddle of it or even influences administrators to adjust counting practices to ensure the “right” candidate wins. Furthermore, the original goal of avoiding protracted and often silly litigation is not accomplished.

Of course, you could take Pitts’ idea still further by prohibiting this type of litigation, but that does not make sense on a policy level because it could lead to the absurd result of not being able to stop administrators from counting votes in a way that everybody agrees is wrong.

There are, of course, other alternatives to coin-flipping in close races, such as automatically holding a new election. However, holding a new election is not as easy as it sounds, and can be downright unfair. As Moritz Fellow Steven Huefner discusses in a 2007 Harvard Journal of Legislation article, new elections are very expensive both for the states and the candidates running. Remedying Election Wrongs, 44 HVJL 265, 296 (2007). For candidates, this means that the candidate with the largest “war chest” left over after the original election has a big advantage in getting out the vote and conducting other types of campaign activities that he or she did not necessarily have in the original election. Furthermore, it may be that in the original election the vote of one candidate was buoyed up by a charismatic candidate of the same party running in a more visible election, in the way that many Democratic candidates were buoyed up by Obama this November. It is not necessarily fair to conduct another election in which that charismatic candidate is no longer running. In general, turnout will generally be lower in the new election because it involves fewer candidates, and it will involve a different mix of voters, so it can hardly be labeled a reasonable facsimile of the election that should have been. These are just some of the problems with holding a new election.

In conclusion, there is no good way that I know of to resolve a close election, only a choice of evils. Coin-flipping and automatically holding a new election are some of the most evil choices so, by process of elimination, traditional election contests start to look pretty good. They are not without their faults, but there is simply nothing better for now, until technology and record-keeping procedures improve to the point where making a meaningful determination of the result of a very very close election becomes possible.

An Extra “Equal Protection” Thought: Local Policy or Local Mistakes?

Although it appears now that the three-judge court in Coleman v. Franken will reject any version of the federal Equal Protection argument that Coleman’s attorneys may attempt to argue, it still remains intellectually interesting to consider whether some variations on the Bush v. Gore theme may have more cogency than others. In a previous post I have already explored some factual distinctions that conceptually might be relevant: for example, the volume of ballots wrongly counted under state law (large or small) in relation to the number of uncounted ballots with the same state-law defect; or the character of the state-law defect in relation to “core” attributes of a voter’s basic eligibility (felon status, missing signature, lack of complete address for ballot’s witness, for example).

Here’s another distinction, based on news reports of some recent trial testimony: what if a sizable number of ballots in some localities were wrongly counted under state law, not because of an accumulation of individualized mistakes by low-level government employees (poll workers, for example), but instead because of a conscious policy decision by a highest county-level official with the authority to make election administration policy for that county? To be sure, in this situation the county-level policy decision is in contravention to state statute, but nonetheless it was a policy decision by the authoritative county official to accept ballots despite what state law says. In effect, it was the “law” of the particular county, which was the “law” enforced on Election Day by that county.

Does the existence of this county-level official “policy” make a difference under federal Equal Protection? I should be clear that I’m not necessarily saying that Coleman has definitely proven factually that such a county-level “policy” did exist. But maybe. There has been testimony apparently that in some counties, as a result of the highest level election officers, there was at least a regular practice of not investigating whether an absentee ballot’s witness was a registered voter, for example. But does a regular practice rise to the level of a policy? Does it matter? Even if there is a relevant distinction for Equal Protection purposes between practice and policy, has Coleman put on enough evidence to prove the existence of a policy, and not just a practice?

One of the main arguments that Franken has been making on why the Minnesota situation is different from Bush v. Gore is the existence of a clear standard in the relevant state statute for accepting or rejecting ballots. Bush v. Gore, by contrast, involved a vague state standard. You don’t have a Bush v. Gore problem, the argument goes, if you have one clear standard in effect that governs the treatment of equivalent ballots throughout the state.

Yet suppose it turns out that in reality there is not one clear statewide standard in operation, but different local standards because some counties have adopted and enforced their own local standards, notwithstanding the existence of the state standard. In this situation, does this local variation in standards and policy (not just in individualized mistakes in the implementation of the single statewide standard) essentially undercut the existence of the single uniform state standard for the purpose of federal Equal Protection analysis? Operationally, is it more like counties coming up with their own local standards in the absence of a uniform state standard?

I don’t know the answer to this question, but it seems worth exploring. Thinking it through may require drawing upon a body of law broader than election law or even Equal Protection law specifically. As part of the enforcement of the Fourteenth Amendment more generally, there has developed over decades a jurisprudence concerning official state conduct that might be in derogation of state law yet nonetheless satisfies the “state action” requirement of the Fourteenth Amendment. In fact, as a law student over twenty years ago, I wrote my “law review note” on this topic: Unauthorized Conduct of State Officials under the Fourteenth Amendment: Hudson v. Palmer and the Resurrection of Dead Doctrine, 85 Columbia L. Rev. 837 (1985). As I recall, relevant to some—but not all of the issues in that field of inquiry—was whether a plaintiff could point to a county-level “custom or policy,” and not just individualized mistakes of local officials. But I have not kept up with developments within that body of law, and I have an impression there have been considerable developments since the mid-1980s. Still, that body of law seems worth consulting for what bearing it might have on the kind of Fourteenth Amendment questions that arguably have been raised by the evidence presented so far in the Coleman v. Franken trial.

In contemplating this scholarly inquiry, I hasten to add what is perhaps obvious: it should make no difference what candidate, or what political party, makes this kind of argument. We can easily imagine any candidate or party arguing in some future case: the Equal Protection principle of Bush v. Gore applies if localities adopt their own policies regarding the counting of ballots, in derogation of a state statute, because that’s a situation where no uniform standard is actually in operation governing the conduct of local officials. Thus, while it is conceded for purposes of this argument that Bush v. Gore does not apply as long as a single uniform standard controls (even if some individual local officials deviate from the standard), Bush v. Gore still governs Equal Protection analysis—or so this argument would go—where the state standard has been countermanded by the highest policymaking authority within the county.

Another point to consider: Bush v. Gore is often considered inapplicable where state law has made a “conscious” choice to permit local variation on a particular question of election administration. A classic example is one mentioned in Bush v. Gore itself: it is presumptively permissible under the Equal Protection Clause for the state to authorize localities to purchase different types of voting machines, even though those machines have different error rates in counting ballots. The state here is making a considered decision to value local autonomy. It can balance that value against competing considerations, including the value of uniform treatment of similarly situated voters.

But where the state has written a uniform rule into its statutes and expected localities to follow that rule, then there has been no state-level policy judgment to encourage (or even tolerate) local policy differences on the point. The fact that the authoritative local officials have gone ahead and adopted their own different local policies anyway cannot be seen as rationally instrumental to the implementation of the relevant state policy. Just the opposite. The local initiative to adopt its own policy is contrary to the state’s asserted goal of uniformity on this point.

The upshot of this analysis might be that it matters how deep and widespread the local policy variance is with the state’s professed desire for uniformity. Maybe if it is just one “renegade” county that for a short time has deviated from the otherwise strictly followed uniform state standard, that fact pattern might not rise to the level of an Equal Protection violation. It’s more like one poll worker at a precinct repeatedly making the same mistake about a state’s voter ID rules. To be sure, the poll worker is not making “policy,” whereas the single “renegade” county is, but an “isolated” instance of local policy variance might matter, compared to widespread local policy variance. Thus, if it turned out that a dozen or more counties had adopted the same policy in contravention of the state’s statute, and had been enforcing their variant policy for years, that might be a very different situation. One might think, or find even evidence, that the Secretary of State has turned a blind eye to this local variance—and then one might reasonably say that the so-called uniform law on the books, looking solely at the state statute, wasn’t really an indication of the true situation. The strictly uniform state standard in the statute had lapsed under the longstanding implementation of local policy variation, and yet there had been no conscious state legislative choice to replace the uniform state standard with a regime of permissible local autonomy. The uncertainty and conflicting signals in state law in this situation might start to resemble the uncertainty of the state standard in Bush v. Gore.

I offer these conjectures without any view of what conclusions ultimately might be drawn from them. I observe only that, analytically, they make possible a narrower form of Equal Protection argument than Coleman appears to having been making so far. But narrower does not necessarily mean correct. Moreover, if these conjectures are at all useful, they indicate that what would separate a valid from invalid Equal Protection argument would be highly fact-dependent (a point consistent with the Court’s opinion in Bush v. Gore). One would need to review the trial record more closely than I have to know whether Coleman has proven the key facts to line up with the narrower Equal Protection theory, even if that theory is sound.

No matter what the facts, a narrower Equal Protection argument would seem to have no chance of prevailing before the three-judge court, given its rulings to date. Nonetheless, from a national perspective, the Coleman v. Franken trial is exposing new nuances and wrinkles to Equal Protection analysis that might become relevant down the road.